-
“Does
Morality Depend on Religion?”
by James Rachels
(Chapter 4 of Rachels’ The Elements of Morality 4th ed)
The
Good consists in always doing what God wills at any particular moment. Emil Brunner, The Divine Imperative (1947) I respect deities. I do not rely upon them. Musashi Miyamoto, at 1. The Presumed
Connection between Morality and Religion
In 1987 Governor
Mario Cuomo of But who, exactly,
would sit on such a panel? The answer tells us a lot about who, in this
country, is thought to speak for morality. The answer is: representatives of
organized religion. According to the New
York Times, “Mr. Cuomo, in an appearance at Few people, at least
in the Why are clergymen
regarded this way? The reason is not that they have proven to be better or
wiser than other people - as a group, they seem to be neither better nor
worse than the rest of us. There is a deeper reason why they are regarded as
having special moral insight. In popular thinking, morality and religion are
inseparable: People commonly believe that morality can be understood only in
the context of religion. So because the clergymen are the spokesmen for
religion, it is assumed that they must be spokesmen for morality as well. It is not hard to see
why people think this. When viewed from a nonreligious perspective, the
universe seems to be a cold, meaningless place, devoid of value and purpose.
In his essay “A Free Man’s Worship,” written in 1902, Bertrand Russell
expressed what he called the “scientific” view of the world: That Man is the product of causes which had no prevision of the end they were achieving; that his origin, his growth, his hopes and fears, his loves and his beliefs, are but the outcome of accidental collocations of atoms; that no fire, no heroism, no intensity of thought and feeling, can preserve an individual life beyond the grave; that all the labours of the ages, all the devotion, all the inspiration, all the noonday brightness of human genius, are destined to extinction in the vast death of the solar system, and that the whole temple of Man’s achievement must inevitable be buried beneath the debris of a universe in ruins - all these things, if not quite beyond dispute, are yet so nearly certain, that no philosophy which rejects them can hope to stand. Only within the scaffolding of these truths, only on the firm foundation of unyielding despair, can the soul’s habitation henceforth be safely built. From a religious
perspective, however, things look very different. Judaism and Christianity
teach that the world was created by a loving, all-powerful God to provide a
home for us. We, in turn, were created in his image, to be his children. Thus
the world is not devoid of meaning and purpose. It is, instead, the arena in
which God’s plans and purposes are realized. What could be more natural,
then, than to think that “morality” is a part of the religious view of the
world, whereas the atheist’s world has no place for values? 2. The Divine
Command Theory
In the major theistic
traditions, including Judaism, Christianity, and Islam, God is conceived as a
lawgiver who has laid down rules that we are to obey. He does not compel us
to obey them. We were created as free agents, so we may choose to accept or
to reject his commandments. But if we are to live as we should live, we must
follow God’s laws. This conception has been elaborated by some theologians
into a theory about the nature of right and wrong known as the Divine Command
Theory. Essentially, this theory says that “morally right” means “commanded
by God” and “morally wrong” means “forbidden by God.” This theory has a
number of attractive features. It immediately solves the old problem about
the objectivity of ethics. Ethics is not merely a matter of personal feeling
or social custom. Whether something is right or wrong is perfectly objective:
It is right if God commands it, wrong if God forbids it. Moreover, the Divine
Command Theory suggests an answer to the perennial question of why anyone
should bother with morality. Why not forget about “ethics” and just look out
for oneself? If immorality is the violation of God’s commandments, there is
an easy answer: On the day of final reckoning, you will be held accountable. There are, however,
serious problems for the theory, Of course, atheists would not accept it,
because thy do no believe that God exists. But there are difficulties even for
believers. The main problem was first noted by Plato, the Greek Philosopher
who lived 400 years before the birth of Jesus. Plato’s writings were
in the form of dialogues, usually between Socrates and one or more
interlocutors. In one of these dialogues, the Euthyphro, there is a discussion concerning whether
“right” can be defined as “that which the gods command.” Socrates is
skeptical and asks: Is conduct right because the gods command it, or do the
gods command it because it is right? This is one of the most famous questions
in the history of philosophy. The British philosopher Antony Flew suggests
that “one good test of a person’s aptitude for philosophy is to discover
whether he can grasp its force and point.” The point is that if
we accept the theological conception of right and wrong, we are caught in a
dilemma. Socrates’ question asks us to clarify what we mean. There are two
things we might mean, and both lead to trouble. 1. First, we might
mean that right conduct is right
because God commands it. For example, according to Exodus 20:16,
God commands us to be truthful. On this option, the reason we should be
truthful is simply that God requires it. Apart from the divine command, truth
telling is neither good nor bad. It is God’s command that makes truthfulness right. But this leads to
trouble, for it represents God’s commands as arbitrary. It means that God
could have given different commands just as easily. He could have commanded
us to be liars, and then lying, not truthfulness, would be right. (You may be
tempted to reply: “But God would never command us to lie.” But why not? If he
did endorse lying, God would not be commanding us to do wrong, because his
command would make it right.) Remember that on this view, honesty was not
right before God commanded it. Therefore, he could have had no more reason to
command it than its opposite; and so, from a moral point of view, his command
is arbitrary. Another problem is
that, on this view, the doctrine of the goodness of God is reduced to
nonsense. It is important to religious believers that God is not only
all-powerful and all-knowing, but the he is also good; yet if we accept the
idea that good and bad are defined by reference to God’s will, this notion is
deprived of any meaning. What could it mean to say that God’s commands are
good? If “X is good” means “X is commanded by God” then “God’s commands are
good” would mean only “God’s commands are commanded by God,” an empty truism.
In 1686, Leibniz observed in his Discourse
on Metaphysics: So
in saying that things are not good by any rule of goodness, but sheerly by
the will of God, it seems to me that one destroys, without realizing it, all
the love of God and all his glory. For why praise him for what he has done if
he would be equally praiseworthy in doing exactly the contrary? Thus if we choose the
first of Socrates’ two options, we seem to be stuck with consequences that
even the most religious people would find unacceptable. 2. There is a way to
avoid theses troublesome consequences. We can take the second
of Socrates’ options. We need not say that right conduct is right because God
commands it. Instead, we may say that God commands us to do certain things because they are right. God, who is
infinitely wise, realizes that truthfulness is better than deceitfulness, and
so he commands us to be truthful; he sees that killing is wrong, and so he
commands us not to kill; and so on for all the moral rules. If we take this
option, we avoid the troublesome consequences that spoiled the first
alternative. God’s commands are not arbitrary; they are the result of his
wisdom in knowing what is best. And the doctrine of the goodness of God is
preserved: To say that his commands are good means that he commands only
what, in his perfect wisdom, he sees to be best. Unfortunately,
however, this second option leads to a different problem, which is equally
troublesome. In taking this option, we have abandoned the theological
conception of right and wrong - when we say that God commands us to be
truthful because truthfulness is right, we are acknowledging a standard of
right and wrong that is independent of God’s will. The rightness exists prior
to and independent of God’s command, and it is the reason for the command.
Thus, if we want to know why we should be truthful, the reply “Because God
commands it” does not really tell us, for we may still ask “But why does God
command it?” and the answer to that
question will provide the underlying reason why truthfulness is a good thing. All this may be
summarized in the following argument: 1.
Suppose God commands us to do what is right. Then either (a) the
right actions are right because he commands them or (b) he commands them
because they are right. 2.
If we take option (a), the God’s commands are, from a moral point
of view, arbitrary; moreover, the doctrine of the goodness of God is rendered
meaningless. 3.
If we take option (b), then we will have acknowledged a standard
of right and wrong that is independent of God’s will. We will have, in
effect, given up the theological conception of right and wrong. 4.
Therefore, we must either regard God’s commands as arbitrary, and
give up the doctrine of the goodness of God, or admit that there is a
standard of right and wrong that is independent of his will, and give up the
theological conception of right and wrong. 5.
From a religious point of view, it is unacceptable to regard God’s
commands as arbitrary or to give up the doctrine of the goodness of God. 6.
Therefore, even from a religious point of view, a standard of
right and wrong that is independent of God’s will must be accepted. Many religious people
believe that they must accept a theological conception of right and wrong
because it would be impious no to do so. They feel, somehow, that if they
believe in God, they should say that right and wrong are to be defined in
terms of his will. But this argument suggests otherwise: It suggests that, on
the contrary, the Divine Command Theory itself leads to impious results, so
that a devout person should not accept it. And in fact, some of the greatest
theologians, such as St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), rejected the theory for
just this reason. Thinkers such as Aquinas connect morality with religion in
a different way. 3. The Theory of
Natural Law
In the history of
Christian thought, the dominant theory of ethics is not the Divine Command
Theory. That honor goes to the Theory of Natural Law. This theory has three
main parts. 1. The Theory of
Natural Law rests upon a certain view of what the world is like. On this
view, the world is a rational order with values and purposes built into its
very nature. This conception derives from the Greeks, whose way of
understanding the world dominated Western thinking for over 1,700 years. A
central feature of this conception was the idea that everything in nature has a purpose. Aristotle
incorporated this idea into his system of thought around 350 B.C. when he
said that, in order to understand anything, four questions must be asked:
What is it? What is it made of? How did it come to exist? And what is it for?
(The answers might be: This is a knife, it is made of metal, it was made by a
craftsman, and it is used for cutting.) Aristotle assumed that the last
question - what is it for? - could sensibly be asked of anything whatever.
“Nature,” he said, “belongs to the class of causes which act for the sake of
something.” It seems obvious that
artifacts such as knives have purposes, because craftsmen have a purpose in
mind when they make them. But what about natural objects that we do not make?
Aristotle believed that they have purposes too. One of his examples was that
we have teeth so that we can chew. Such biological examples are quite
persuasive; each part of our bodies does seem, intuitively, to have a special
purpose - eyes are for seeing, the heart is for pumping blood, and so on. But
Aristotle’s claim was not limited to organic beings. According to him, everything has a purpose. He
thought, to take a different sort of example, that rain falls so that plants
can grow. As odd as it may seem to a modern reader, Aristotle was perfectly
serious about this. He considered other alternatives, such as that the rain
falls “of necessity” and that this helps the plants only by “coincidence,”
and rejected them. The world, therefore,
is an orderly, rational system, with each thing having its own proper place
and serving its own special purpose. There is a neat hierarchy: The rain
exists for the sake of the plants, the plants exist for the sake of the
animals, and the animals exist - of course - for the sake of people, whose
well- being is the point of the whole arrangement. [W]e must believe,
first that plants exist for the sake of animals, second that all other
animals exist for the sake of man, tame animals for the use he can make of them
as well as for the food they provide; and as for wild animals, most though
not all of these can be used for food or are useful in other ways; clothing
and instruments can be made out of them. If then we are right in believing
that nature makes nothing without some end in view, nothing to no purpose, it
must be that nature has made all things specifically for the sake of man. This seems stunningly
anthropocentric. Aristotle may be forgiven, however, when we consider that
virtually every important thinker in out history has entertained some such
thought. Humans are a remarkably vain species. The Christian
thinkers who came later found this view of the world to be perfectly
congenial. Only one thing was missing: God was needed to make the picture
complete. (Aristotle has denied that God was a necessary part of the picture.
For him, the worldview we have outlined was not religious; it was simply a
description of how things are.) Thus the Christian thinkers said that the
rain falls to help the plants because
that is what the Creator intended, and the animals are for human
use because that is what God made
them for. Values and purposes were, therefore, conceived to be a
fundamental part of the nature of things, because the world was believed to
have been created according to a divine plan. 2. A corollary of
this way of thinking is that “the laws of nature” not only describe how
things are, they specify
how things ought to be as
well. Things are as they ought to be when they are serving their natural
purposes. When they do not, or cannot, serve those purposes, things have gone
wrong. Eyes that cannot see are defective, and drought is a natural evil; the
badness of both is explained by reference to natural law. But there are also
implications for human conduct. Moral rules are not viewed as deriving from
the laws of nature. Some ways of behaving are said to be “natural,” while
other are “unnatural”; and “unnatural” acts are said to be morally wrong. Consider, for
example, the duty of beneficence. We are morally required to be concerned for
our neighbor’s welfare as we are for our own. Why? According to the Theory of
Natural Law, beneficence is natural for us, considering the kind of creatures
we are. We are by our nature social creatures who want and need the company
of other people. It is also part of our natural makeup that we care about
others. Someone who does not care at all for others - who really does not
care, through and through - is seen as deranged, in the terms of modern
psychology, a sociopath. A malicious personality is defective, just as eyes
are defective if they cannot see. And, it may be added, this is true because
we were created by God, with a specific “human” nature, as part of his
overall plan for the world. The endorsement of
beneficence is relatively uncontroversial. Natural law theory has also been
used, however, to support moral views that are more contentious. Religious
thinkers have traditionally condemned “deviant” sexual practices, and the
theoretical justification of their opposition has come more often than not
from theory of natural law. If everything has a purpose, what is the purpose
of sex? The obvious answer is procreation. Sexual activity that is not
connected with making babies can therefore be viewed as “unnatural,” and so
such practices as masturbation and oral sex - not to mention gay sex - can be
condemned for this reason. This way of thinking about sex dates back to at
least to Outside the Catholic
Church, the Theory of Natural Law has few advocates today. It is generally
rejected for two reasons. First, it seems to involve a confusion of “is” and
“ought.” In the 18th century David Hume pointed out that what is the case and what ought to be the case are
logically different notions, and no conclusion about one follows from the
other. We can say that people are naturally disposed to be beneficent, but it
does not follow that they should be beneficent. Similarly, it may be that sex
does produce babies, but it does not follow that sex ought or ought not to be
engaged in only for that purpose. Facts are one thing; values are another.
The Theory of Natural Law seems to conflate them. Second, the Theory of
Natural Law has gone out of fashion (although that does not, of course, prove
it is false) because the view of the world on which it rests is out of
keeping with modern science. The world as described by Galileo, Thus modern science
gives us a picture of the world as a realm of facts, where the only “natural
laws” are the laws of physics, chemistry, and biology, working blindly and
without purpose. Whatever values may be, they are not part of the natural
order. As for the idea that “nature has made all things specifically for the
sake of man,” that is only human vanity. To the extent that one accepts the
worldview of modern science, then, one will be skeptical of the Theory of
Natural Law. It is no accident that the theory was a product, not of modern
thought, but of the Middle Ages. 3. The third part of
the theory addresses the question of moral knowledge. How are we to go about
determining what is right and what is wrong? The Divine Command Theory says
that we must consult God’s commandments. The Theory of Natural Law gives a
different answer. The “natural laws” that specify what we should do are laws
of reason, which we are able to grasp because God, the author of the natural
order, has made us rational beings with the power to understand that order.
Therefore, the Theory of Natural Law endorses the familiar idea that the
right thing to do is whatever course of conduct has the best reasons on its
side. To use the traditional terminology, moral judgments are “dictates of
reason.” St. Thomas Aquinas, the greatest of the natural-law theorists, wrote
in his masterpiece the Summa
Theologica that “To disparage the dictate of reason is equivalent
to condemning the command of God.” This means that the
religious believer has no special access to moral truth. The believer and the
nonbeliever are in the same position. God has given both the same powers of
reasoning; and so believer and nonbeliever alike may listen to reason and
follow its directives. They function as moral agents in the same way, even
though the nonbelievers’ lack of faith prevents them from realizing that God
is the author of the rational order in which they participate and which their
moral judgments express. In an important
sense, this leaves morality independent of religion. Religious belief does
not affect the calculation of what is best, and the results of moral inquiry
are religiously “neutral.” In this way, even though they may disagree about
religion, believers and nonbelievers inhabit the same moral universe. 4. Religion and Particular Moral IssuesSome religious people
will find the preceding discussion unsatisfying. It will seem too abstract to
have any bearing on their actual moral lives. For them, the connection
between morality and religion is an immediate, practical matter that centers
on particular moral issues. It doesn’t matter whether right and wrong are
“defined” in terms of God’s will or whether moral laws are laws of nature:
Whatever the merits of such theories, there are still the moral teachings of
one’s religion about particular issues. The teachings of the Scriptures and
the church are regarded as authoritative, determining the moral positions one
must take. To mention only one example, many Christians think that they have
no choice but to oppose abortion because it is condemned both by the church
and (they assume) by the Scriptures. Are there, in fact,
distinctively religious positions on major moral issues, which believer are
bound to accept? If so, are those positions different from the views that
other people might reach simply by trying to reason out the best thing to do?
The rhetoric of the pulpit suggests that the answer to both questions is yes.
But there are several reasons to think otherwise. In the first place,
it is often difficult to find specific moral guidance in the Scriptures. Our
problems are not the same as the problems faced by the Jews and the early
Christians many centuries ago; thus, it is not surprising that the Scriptures
might be silent about moral issues that seem urgent to us. The Bible contains
a number of general precepts, such a the injunctions to love one’s neighbor
and to treat others as one would wish to be treated oneself, that might be
thought relevant to a variety of issues. But worthy as those precepts are,
they do not yield definite answers about exactly what position one should
take concerning the rights of workers, the extinction of species, the funding
of medical research, and so on. Another problem is
that in many instances the Scriptures and church tradition are ambiguous.
Authorities disagree, leaving the believer in the awkward position of having
to choose which element of the tradition to accept and which authority to
believe. Read plainly, for example, the New Testament condemns being rich,
and there is a long tradition of self-denial and charitable giving that
affirms this teaching. But there is also an obscure Old Testament figure
named Jabez who asked God to “enlarge my territories” (I Chronicles 4:10),
and God did. A recent book urging Christians to adopt Jabez as their model
became a best-seller. Thus when people say
that their moral views are derived from their religious commitments, they are
often mistaken. In reality, something very different is going on. They are
making up their minds about the moral issues first and then interpreting the
Scriptures, or church tradition, in such a way as to support the moral
conclusion they have already reached. Of course this does not happen in every
case, but it seems fair to say that it happens often. The question of riches
is one example; abortion is another. In the debate over
abortion, religious issues are never far from the center of discussion.
Religious conservatives hold that the fetus is a human being from the moment
of conception, and so they say killing it is really a form of murder. They do
not believe it should be the mother’s choice whether to have an abortion,
because that would be like saying she is free to commit murder. The key premise in
the conservative argument is that the fetus is a human being from the moment
of conception. The fertilized ovum is not merely a potential human being but
an actual human being with a full-fledged right to life. Liberals, of course,
deny this - they say that, at least during the early weeks of pregnancy, the
embryo is something less than a full human being. The debate over the
humanity of the fetus is enormously complicated, but here we are concerned
with just one small part of it. Conservative Christians sometimes say that,
regardless of how secular thought might view the fetus, the Christian view is
that the fetus is a human being from its very beginning. But is this view
mandatory for Christians? What evidence might be offered to show this? One
might appeal to the Scriptures or to church tradition. The
Scriptures.
It is difficult to derive a prohibition of abortion from either the Jewish or
the Christian Scriptures. The Bible does not speak plainly on the matter.
There are certain passages, however, that are often quoted by conservatives
because they seem to suggest that fetuses have full human status. One of the
most frequently cited passages is from the first chapter of Jeremiah, in
which God is quoted as saying: “Before I formed you in the womb I knew you,
and before you were born I consecrated you.” These words are presented as
though they were God’s endorsement of the conservative positions: They are
taken to mean that the unborn, as well as the born, are “consecrated” to God. In context, however,
these words obviously mean something quite different. Suppose we read the
whole passage in which they occur: Now
the word of the Lord came to me saying, “Before I formed you in the womb I
knew you, and before you were born I consecrated you; I appointed you a
prophet to the nations.” Then
I said, “Ah, Lord God! Behold, I do not know how to speak, for I am only a
youth.” But the Lord said to me, “Do
not say I am only a youth’ for to all
to whom I send you you shall go, and whatever I command you you shall speak.
Be not afraid of them, for I am with you to deliver you,” says the Lord. Neither abortion, the
sanctity of fetal life, nor anything else of the kind is being discussed in
this passage. Instead, Jeremiah is asserting his authority as a prophet. He
is saying, in effect, “God authorized me to speak for him; even though I
resisted, he commanded me to speak.” But Jeremiah puts the point more poetically;
he has God saying that God had intended him to be a prophet even before
Jeremiah was born. This often happens
when the Scriptures are cited in connection with controversial moral issues.
A few words are lifted from a passage that is concerned with something
entirely different from the issue at hand, and those words are then construed
in a way that supports a favored moral position. When this happens, is it
accurate to say that the person is “following the moral teachings of the
Bible?” Or is it more accurate to say the he or she is searching the
Scriptures for support of a moral view he or she already happens to think is
right, and reading the desired conclusion into the Scriptures? If the latter,
it suggests an especially impious attitude - an attitude that assumes God
himself must share one’s own moral opinions. In the case of the passage from
Jeremiah, it is hard to see how an impartial reader could think the words
have anything to do with abortion, even by implication. The scriptural passage
that comes closest to making a specific judgment about the moral status of
fetuses occurs in the 21st chapter of Exodus. This chapter is part of a
detailed description of the law of the ancient Israelites. Here the penalty
for murder is said to be death; however, it is also said that if a pregnant
woman is caused to have a miscarriage, the penalty is only a fine, to be paid
by her husband. Murder was not a category that included fetuses. The Law of
Israel apparently regarded fetuses as something less than full human beings. Church
Tradition.
Even if there is little scriptural basis for it, the contemporary church’s
stand is strongly antiabortion. The typical churchgoer will hear ministers,
priests, and bishops denouncing abortion in the strongest terms. It is no
wonder, then, that many people feel that their religious commitment binds
them to oppose abortion. But it is worth
noting that the church has not always taken this view. In fact, the idea that
the fetus is a human being “from the moment of conception” is a relatively
new idea, even within the Christian church. St. Thomas Aquinas held that an
embryo does not have a soul until several weeks into the pregnancy. Aquinas
accepted Aristotle’s view that the soul is the “substantial form” of man. We need
not go into this somewhat technical notion, except to note that one
implication is that one cannot have a human soul until one’s body has a
recognizably human shape. Aquinas knew that a human embryo does not have a
human shape “from the moment of conception,” and he drew the indicated
conclusion. Aquinas’s view of the matter was officially accepted by the
church at the Council of Vienne in 1312, and to this day it has never been
officially repudiated. However, in the 17th
century, a curious view of fetal development came to be accepted, and this
has unexpected consequences for the church’s view of abortion. Peering
through primitive microscopes at fertilized ova, some scientists imagined
that they saw tiny, perfectly formed people. They called the little person a
“homunculus,” and the idea took hold that from the very beginning the human
embryo is a fully formed creature that needs only to get bigger and bigger
until it is ready to be born. If the embryo has a
human shape from the moment of conception, then it follows, according to
Aristotle’s and Aquinas’s philosophy, that it can have a human soul from the
moment of conception. The church drew this conclusion and embraced the
conservative view of abortion. The “homunculus,” it said, is clearly a human
being, and so it is wrong to kill it. However, as our
understanding of human biology progressed, scientists began to realize that
this view of fetal development was wrong. There is no homunculus; that was a
mistake. Today we know that Aquinas’s original thought was right - embryos
start out as a cluster of cells; “human form” comes later. But when the
biological error was corrected, the church’s moral view did not revert to the
older position. Having adopted the theory that the fetus is a human being
“from the moment of conception,” the church did not let it go and held fast
to the conservative view of abortion. The council of Because the church
did not traditionally regard abortion as a serious moral issue, Western law
(which developed under the church’s influence) did not traditionally treat
abortion as a crime. Under the English common law, abortion was tolerated
even if performed late in the pregnancy. In the The purpose of
reviewing this history is not to suggest that the contemporary church’s
position is wrong. For all that has been said here, its view may be right. I
only want to make a point about the relation between religious authority and
moral judgment. Church tradition, like Scripture, is reinterpreted by every
generation to support its favored moral views. Abortion is just an example of
this. We could just as easily have used shifting moral and religious views
about slavery, or the status of women, or capital punishment, as our example.
In each instance, people’s moral convictions are not so much derived from
their religion as superimposed on it. The various arguments
in this chapter point to a common conclusion. Right and wrong are not to be
defined in terms of God’s will; morality is a matter of reason and
conscience, not religious faith; and in any case, religious considerations do
not provide definitive solutions to the specific moral problems that confront
us. Morality and religion are, in a word, different. Because this conclusion
is contrary to conventional wisdom, it may strike some readers as
antireligious. Therefore, it should be emphasized that this conclusion has
not been reached by questioning the validity of religion. The arguments we
have considered do not assume that Christianity or any other theological
system is false; these arguments merely show that even if such a system is
true, morality remains an independent matter. |