MIME-Version: 1.0 Content-Type: multipart/related; boundary="----=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910" This document is a Single File Web Page, also known as a Web Archive file. If you are seeing this message, your browser or editor doesn't support Web Archive files. Please download a browser that supports Web Archive, such as Windows® Internet Explorer®. ------=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910 Content-Location: file:///C:/D1123EF9/Bedau--TheCaseAgainsttheDeathPenalty.htm Content-Transfer-Encoding: quoted-printable Content-Type: text/html; charset="us-ascii" The Case Against the Death Penalty

The Case Aga= inst The Death Penalty

by Hugo Adam Bedau

Preface

Hugo Adam Bedau is Fletcher Professor of Philosophy = at Tufts University. He has written and edited a number of books on political philosophy and on capital punishment, including Death is Different (1987) and = The Death Penalty in Amer= ica, 3rd edition (1982 ). He gratefully acknowledges = the assistance of Henry Schwarzschild, Director Emeritus of the ACLU Capital Punishment Project.

The American Civil Liberties Union holds that the death penalty inherently violates the constitutional ban aga= inst cruel and unusual punishment and the guarantee of due process of law and the equal protection of the laws. The imposition of the death penalty is inconsistent with fundamental values of our democratic system. The state sh= ould not arrogate unto itself the right to kill human beings, especially when it kills with premeditation and ceremony, under color of law, in our names, and when it does so in an arbitrary and discriminatory fashion. In the judgment= of the ACLU, capital punishment is an intolerable denial of civil liberties. We shall therefore continue to seek to prevent executions and to abolish capit= al punishment by litigation, legislation , commutat= ion, or by the weight of a renewed public outcry against this brutal and brutali= zing institution.

Capital Punishment Project
American Civil Liberties Union
122 Maryland Avenue, N.E.
Washington, D.C. 20002

ISBN 0-86566-063-8
(c) American Civil Liberties Union
Permission to reprint, with credit given to the source, is granted.


Introduction

In 1972, the Supreme Court declared that under then existing laws "the imposition and carrying out of the death penalty ... constitutes cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth and Fourteenth Amendments." (Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S.238) The majority = of the Court concentrated its objections on the way death-penalty laws had been applied, finding the result so "harsh, freakish, and arbitrary" a= s to be constitutionally unacceptable. Making the nationwide impact of its decis= ion unmistakable, the Court summarily reversed death sentences in the many cases then before it, which involved a wide range of state statutes, crimes, and factual situations.

But within four years after the Fu= rman decision, more than 600 persons had been sentenced to death under new capital-punishment statutes that provided guidance for the jury's sentencing discretion. These statutes typically require a bifurcated (two-stage) trial procedure, in which the jury first determines guilt or innocence and then chooses imprisonment or death in the light of aggravating or mitigating circumstances.

In July 1976, the Supreme Court mo= ved in the opposite direction, holding that "the punishment of death does = not invariably violate the Constitution." The Court ruled that these new statutes contained "objective standards to guide, regularize, and make rationally reviewable the process for imposing the sentence of death." (Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S.153) Thus the states as well as Congress have had for some years constitutionally valid statutory = models for death-penalty laws, and more than three dozen state legislatures have enacted death penalty statutes patterned after those the Court upheld in Gr= egg. In recent years, Congress has enacted death penalty statutes for peacetime espionage by military personnel and for drug-related murders.

Executions resumed in 1977, and by= the early 1990s nearly three thousand persons were under sentence of death and = more than 180 had been executed.

Despite the Supreme Court's 1976 ruling in Gregg v. Georgia, the ACLU continues to oppose capital punishment= on moral and practical, as well as on constitutional, grounds:

Two conclusions buttress our entire case: Capital punishment does not deter cri= me, and the death penalty is uncivilized in theory and unfair and inequitable in practice.

Deterrence

The argument most often cited in support of capital punishment is that the thre= at of executions deters capital crimes more effectively than imprisonment. This claim is plausible, but the facts do not support it. The death penalty fail= s as a deterrent for several reasons.

--1--
Any punishment can be an effective deterrent only if it is consistently and= promptly employed. Capital punishment cannot be administered to meet these condition= s.

Only a small proportion of first-degree murderers is sentenced to death, an= d even fewer are executed. Although death sentences since 1980 have increased in number to about 250 per year,(1) this is still only 1 per cent of all homic= ides known to the police.(2) Of all those convicted on a charge of criminal homicide, only 2 percent -- about 1 in 50 -- are eventually sentenced to death.(3)

The possibility of increasing the number of convicted murderers sentenced to death and executed by enacting mandatory death penalty laws was ruled unconstitutional in 1976 (Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280).

Considerable delay in carrying out= the death sentence is unavoidable, given the procedural safeguards required by = the courts in capital cases. Starting with empaneling the trial jury, murder trials take far longer when the death penalty is involve= d. Post-conviction appeals in death-penalty cases are far more frequent as wel= l. All these factors increase the time and cost of administering criminal justice.=

The sobering lesson is that we can reduce such delay and costs only by abandoning the procedural safeguards and constitutional rights of suspects, defendants, and convicts, with the atten= dant high risk of convicting the wrong person and executing the innocent. <= /o:p>

--2--
Persons who commit murder and other crimes of personal violence either premeditate them or they do not. If the crime is premeditated, the criminal ordinarily concentrates on escaping detection, arrest, and conviction. The threat of even the severest punishment will not deter those who expect to escape detection and arrest. If the crime is not premeditated, then it is impossible to imagine how the threat of any punishment could deter it. Most capital crimes are committed during moments of great emotional stress or un= der the influence of drugs or alcohol, when logical thinking has been suspended. Impulsive or expressive violence is inflicted by persons heedless of the co= nsequences to themselves as well as to others.

Gangland killings, air piracy, drive-by shootings, and kidnapping for ransom are among the graver felonies that continue to be committed because some individuals think they are too clever to get caught. Political terrorism is usually committed in the name = of an ideology that honors its martyrs; trying to cope with it by threatening death for terrorists is futile. Such threats leave untouched the underlying causes and ignore the many political and diplomatic sanctions (such as trea= ties against asylum for international terrorists) that could appreciably lower t= he incidence of terrorism.

The attempt to reduce murders in t= he illegal drug trade by the threat of severe punishment ignores this fact: An= yone trafficking in illegal drugs is already betting his life in violent competi= tion with other dealers. It is irrational to think that the death penalty--a rem= ote threat at best -- will deter murders committed in drug turf wars or by street-level dealers.

--3--
If, however, severe punishment can deter crime, then long term imprisonment= is severe enough to cause any rational person not to commit violent crimes. The vast preponderance of the evidence shows that the death penalty is no more effective than imprisonment in deterring murder and that it may even be an incitement to criminal violence in certain cases.

Actual experience establishes these conclusions beyond a reasonable doubt. No comparable body of evidence contradicts them.

Three investigations since Furman, using methods pioneered by economists, reported findings in the opposite direction.(11) Subsequently, several qualified investigators have independently examined these claims, and all have reject= ed them.(12) The National Academy of Sciences, in its thorough report on the effects of criminal sanctions on crime rates, concluded: "It seems unthinkable to us to base decisions on the use of the death penalty" on such "fragile" and "uncertain" results. "We see too many plausible explanations for [these] findings ... other than the theory = that capital punishment deters murder."(13)

Furthermore, cases have been clinically documented where the death penalty actually incited the capital crimes it was supposed to deter. These include instances of the so-called suicide-by-execution syndrome -- persons who wanted but feared to take their own life and committed murder so that society would kill them.(14)

It must, of course, be conceded th= at inflicting the death penalty guarantees that the condemned person will comm= it no further crimes. This is an incapacitative, n= ot a deterrent, effect of executions. Furthermore, it is too high a price to pay when studies show that very few convicted murderers ever commit another cri= me of violence.(15) A recent study examined the pri= son and post-release records of 533 prisoners on death row in 1972 whose senten= ces were reduced to life by the Supreme Court's ruling in Furman. The research showed that 6 had committed another murder. But the same study showed that = in 4 other cases, an innocent man had been sentenced to death.(16)

Recidivism among murderers does occasionally happen. But it happens less frequently than most people believ= e; the media rarely distinguish between a paroled murderer who murders again a= nd other murderers who have a previous criminal record but not for homicide.

There is no way to predict which convicted murderers will kill again. Repeat murders could be prevented only= by executing all those convicted of criminal homicide. Such a policy is too inhumane and brutal to be taken seriously. Society would never tolerate doz= ens of executions daily, yet nothing less would suffice. Equally effective but = far less inhumane is a policy of life imprisonment without the possibility of parole.

Unfairness

Constitutional due process as well as elementary justice require that the judicial functions of trial and sentencing be conducted with fundamental fairness, especially where the irreversible sanction of the death penalty is involved. In murder cases (since 1930, 99 percent of all executions have be= en for this crime), there has been substantial evidence to show that courts ha= ve been arbitrary, racially biased, and unfair in the way in which they have sentenced some persons to prison but others to death.

Racial discrimination was one of t= he grounds on which the Supreme Court relied in Furman in ruling the death pen= alty unconstitutional. Half a century ago, Gunnar Myrdal, in his classic American Dilemma (1944), reported that "the South makes the widest application = of the death penalty, and Negro criminals come in for much more than their sha= re of the executions." Statistics confirm this discrimination, only it is= not confined to the South. Between 1930 and 1990, 4,016 persons were executed in the United States. Of these, 2,129 (or 53 percent) were black. For the crim= e of murder, 3,343 were executed; 1,693 (or 51 percent) were black.(17) During these years African-Americans were about 12 per cent of the nation's population.

The nation's death rows have alway= s had a disproportionately large population of African-Americans, relative to the= ir fraction of the total population. Over the past century, black offenders, as compared with white, were often executed for crimes less often receiving the death penalty, such as rape and burglary. (Between 1930 and 1976, 455 men w= ere executed for rape, of whom 405 (or 90 percent) were black.) A higher percen= tage of the blacks who were executed were juveniles; and blacks were more often executed than were whites without having their conviction reviewed by any higher court.(18)

In recent years, it has been widely believed that such flagrant discrimination is a thing of the past. Since the revival of the death penalty in the mid-1970s, about half of those on death= row at any given time have been black(19) -- a disproportionately large fraction given the black/white ratio of the total population, but not so obviously unfair if judged by the fact that roughly = 50 percent of all those arrested for murder were also black.(20) Nevertheless, when those under death sentence are examined more closely, it turns out that race is a decisive factor after all.

An exhaustive statistical study of racial discrimination in capital cases in Georgia, for example, showed that "the average odds of receiving a death sentence among all indicted cas= es were 4.3 times higher in cases with white victims."(21) In 1987 these = data were placed before the Supreme Court in McCleskey v. Kemp and the Court did not dispute the statistical evidence. The Court did hold, however, that the evidence failed to show that there was "a constitutionally significant risk of racial bias....&qu= ot; . (481 U.S. 279)

In 1990, the U.S. General Accounti= ng Office reported to the Congress the results of its review of empirical stud= ies on racism and the death penalty. The GAO concluded: "Our synthesis of = the 28 studies shows a pattern of evidence indicating racial disparities in the charging, sentencing, and imposition of the death penalty after the Furman decision" and that "race of victim influence was found at all sta= ges of the criminal justice system process...." .

These results cannot be explained = away by relevant non-racial factors (such as prior criminal record or type of crime), and they lead to a very unsavory conclusion: In the trial courts of this nation, even at the present time, the killing of a white is treated mu= ch more severely than the killing of a black. Of the 168 persons executed betw= een January 1977 and April 1992, only 29 had been convicted of the killing of a non-white, and only one of these 29 was himself white.(23) Where the death penalty is involved, our criminal justice system essentially reserves the d= eath penalty for murderers (regardless of their race) who kill white victims.

Both sex and socio-economic class = are also factors that enter into determining who receives a death sentence and = who is executed. During the 1980s and aerially 1990s, only about I percent of a= ll those on death row were women,(24) even though women commit about 15 percen= t of all criminal homicides.(25) A third or more of the women under death senten= ce were guilty of killing men who had victimized them with years of violent abuse.(26) Since 1930, only 33 women (12 of them black) have been executed = in the United States.(27)

Discrimination against the poor (a= nd in our society racial minorities are disproportionately poor) is also well established. "Approximately ninety percent of those on death row could= not afford to hire a lawyer when they were tried."(28) A defendant's pover= ty, lack of firm social roots in the community, inadequate legal representation= at trial or on appeal--all these have been common factors among death-row populations. As Justice William O. Douglas noted in Furman, "One searc= hes our chronicles in vain for the execution of any member of the affluent stra= ta in this society." (408 U.S. 238)

The demonstrated inequities in the actual administration of capital punishment should tip the balance against = it in the judgment of fair-minded and impartial observers. "Whatever else might be said for the use of death as a punishment, one lesson is clear from experience: this is a power that we cannot exercise fairly and without discrimination."(29)

Justice John Marshall Harlan, writ= ing for the Court, noted: "...the history of capital punishment for homicides...reveals continual efforts, uniformly unsuccessful, to identify before the fact those homicides for which the slayer should die.... Those w= ho have come to grips with the hard task of actually attempting to draft means= of channeling capital sentencing discretion have confirmed the lesson taught by history.... To identify before the fact those characteristics of criminal homicides and their perpetrators which call for the death penalty, and to express these characteristics in language which can be fairly understood and applied by the sentencing authority, appears to be tasks which are beyond present human ability." (McGautha v. Calif= ornia, 402 U.S . 183 (1971))

Yet in the Gregg decision, the majority of the Supreme Court abandoned the wisdom of Justice Harlan and ru= led as though the new guided-discretion statutes could accomplish the impossibl= e. The truth is that death statutes approved by the Court "do not effecti= vely restrict the discretion of juries by any real standards. They never will. N= o society is going to kill everybody who meets certain preset verbal requirements, pu= t on the statute books without awareness of coverage of the infinity of special factors the real world can produce."(30)

Even if these statutes were to suc= ceed in guiding the jury's choice of sentence, a vast reservoir of unfettered discretion remains: the prosecutor's decision to prosecute for a capital or lesser crime, the court's willingness to accept or reject a guilt y plea, t= he jury's decision to convict for second-degree murder or manslaughter rather = than capital murder, the determination of the defendant's sanity, the final deci= sion by the governor on clemency.

Discretion in the criminal-justice system is unavoidable. The history of capital punishment in American society clearly shows the desire to mitigate the harshness of this penalty by narro= wing its scope. Discretion, whether authorized by statutes or by t heir silence,= has been the main vehicle to this end. But when discretion is used, as it always has been, to mark for death the poor, the friendless, the uneducated, the members of racial minorities, and the despised, then discretion becomes injustice.

Thoughtful citizens, who in contemplating capital punishment in the abstract might support it, must con= demn it in actual practice.

Inevitability of Error

Unlike all other criminal punishments, the death penalty is uniquely irrevocable. Speaking to the French Chamber of Deputies in 1830, years after the excesse= s of the French Revolution, which he had witnessed, the Marquis de Lafayette sai= d, "I shall ask for the abolition of the punishment of death until I have= the infallibility of human judgment demonstrated to me."(31) Although some proponents of capital punishment would argue that its merits are worth the occasional execution of innocent people, most would also insist that there = is little likelihood of the innocent being executed. Yet a large body of evidence shows that innocent people are often convicted of crimes, including capital crimes and that some of them have been executed.

Since 1900, in this country, there have been on the average more than four cases per year in which an entirely innocent person was convicted of murder. Scores of these persons were sente= nced to death. In many cases, a reprieve or commutation arrived just hours, or e= ven minutes, before the scheduled execution. These erroneous convictions have occurred in virtually every jurisdiction from one end of the nation to the other. Nor have they declined in recent years, despite the new death penalty statutes approved by the Supreme Court.(32) Consider this handful of representative cases:

Each of the five stories told above has a reassuring ending: The innocent prison= er is saved from execution and is released. But when prisoners are executed, no legal forum exists in which unanswered questions about their guilt can be resolved. In May 1992, Roger Keith Coleman was executed in Virginia despite widely publicized doubts surrounding his guilt and evidence that pointed to another person as the murderer -- evidence that was never submitted at his trial. Not until late in the appeal process did anyone take seriously the possibility that the state was about to kill an innocent man, and then effo= rts to delay or nullify his execution failed. Was Coleman really innocent? At t= he time of his execution, his case was marked with many of the features found = in other cases where the defendant was eventually cleared. Were Coleman still = in prison, his friends and attorneys would have a strong incentive to resolve these questions. But with Coleman dead, further inquiry into the facts of t= he crime for which h e was convicted is unlikely.

Overzealous prosecution, mistaken = or perjured testimony, faulty police work, coerced confessions, the defendant's previous criminal record, inept defense counsel, seemingly conclusive circumstantial evidence, community pressure for a conviction -- such factors help explain why the judicial system cannot guarantee that justice will nev= er miscarry. And when it does miscarry, volunteers outside the criminal justice system -- newspaper reporters, for example -- and not the police or prosecu= tors are the ones who rectify the errors. To retain the death penalty in the fac= e of the demonstrable failures of the system is unacceptable, especially as there are no strong counterbalancing factors in favor of the death penalty. =

Barbarity

The traditional mode of execution, still available in a few states, is hanging. Death on the gallows is easily bungled: If the drop is too short, there wil= l be a slow and agonizing death by strangulation. If the drop is too long, the h= ead will be torn off.

Two states, Idaho and Utah, still authorize the firing squad. The prisoner is strapped into a chair, and hood= ed. A target is pinned to the chest. Five marksmen, one with blanks, take aim a= nd fire.

Electrocution has been the most wi= dely used form of execution in this country in this century. The condemned priso= ner is led--or dragged--into the death chamber, strapped into the chair, and electrodes are fastened to head and legs. When the switch is thrown the body strains, jolting as the voltage is raised and lowered. Often smoke rises fr= om the head. There is the awful odor of burning flesh. No one knows how long electrocuted individuals retain consciousness.

In 1983, the electrocution of John Evans in Alabama was described by an eyewitness as follows: "At 8:30 p= .m. the first jolt of 1900 volts of electricity passed through Mr. Evans' body.= It lasted thirty seconds. Sparks and flames erupted ... from the electrode tie= d to Mr. Evans' left leg. His body slammed against the straps holding him in the electric chair and his fist clenched permanently. The electrode apparently burst from the strap holding it in place. A large puff of grayish smoke and sparks poured out from under the hood that covered Mr. Evans' face. An overpowering stench of burnt flesh and clothing began pervading the witness room. Two doctors examined Mr. Evans and declared that he was not dead.

"The electrode on the left leg was refastened.... Mr. Evans was administered a second thirty second jolt of electricity. The stench of burning flesh was nauseating. More smoke emanated from his leg and head. Again, the doctors examined Mr. Evans. [They] report= ed that his heart was still beating, and that he was still alive. At that time= , I asked the prison commissioner, who was communicating on an open telephone l= ine to Governor George Wallace, to grant clemency on the grounds that Mr. Evans= was being subjected to cruel and unusual punishment. The request ... was denied= .

"At 8:40 p.m., a third charge= of electricity, thirty seconds in duration, was passed through Mr. Evans' body= . At 8:44, the doctors pronounced him dead. The execution of John Evans took fourteen minutes."(38) Afterwards, officials were embarrassed by what = one observer called the "barbaric ritual." The prison spokesman remar= ked, "This was supposed to be a very clean manner of administering death."(39)

An attempt to improve on electrocu= tion was the gas chamber. The prisoner is strapped into a chair, a container of sulfuric acid underneath. The chamber is sealed, and cyanide is dropped into the acid to form lethal gas. Here is an account of the 1992 execution in Arizona of Don Harding, as reported in the dissent by U. S. Supreme Court Justice John Paul Stevens:

"When the fumes enveloped Don= 's head he took a quick breath. A few seconds later he again looked in my direction. His face was red and contorted as if he were attempting to fight through tremendous pain. His mouth was pursed shut and his jaw was clenched tight. Don then look several more quick gulps of the fumes.

"At this point Don's body sta= rted convulsing violently....His face and body fumed a deep red and the veins in= his temple and neck began to bulge until I thought they might explode.

"After about a minute Don's f= ace leaned partially forward, but he was still conscious. Every few seconds he continued to gulp in. He was shuddering uncontrollably and his body was rac= ked with spasms. His head continued to snap back. His hands were clenched.

"After several more manuals, = the most violent of the convulsions subsided. At this time the muscles along Do= n's left arm and back began twitching in a wavelike motion under his skin. Spit= tle drooled from his mouth.

"Don did not stop moving for approximately eight minutes, and after that he continued to twitch and jerk= for another minute. Approximately two minutes later, we were told by a prison official that the execution was complete.

"Don Harding took ten minutes= and thirty one seconds to die." (Gomez v. U.S. District Court, 112 S.Ct. 1652)

The latest mode of inflicting the death penalty, enacted into law by nearly two dozen states, is lethal injection, first used in Texas in 1982. It is easy to overstate the humanen= ess and efficacy of this method. There is no way of knowing that it is really painless. As the U.S. Court of Appeals observed, there is "substantial= and uncontroverted evidence ... that execution by lethal injection poses a seri= ous risk of cruel, protracted death.... Even a slight error in dosage or administration can leave a prisoner conscious but paralyzed while dying, a sentient witness of his or her own asphyxiation." (Chaney v. Heckler, = 718 F.2d 1174 [1983])

Nor does the execution always proc= eed smoothly as planned. In 1985 "the authorities repeatedly jabbed needles into ... Stephen Morin, when they had trouble finding a usable vein because= he had been a drug abuser."(40) In 1988, during the execution of Raymond Landry, "a tube attached to a needle inside the inmate's right arm beg= an leaking, sending the lethal mixture shooting across the death chamber toward witnesses."(41)

Indeed, by its veneer of decency a= nd by subtle analogy with life-saving medical practice, death by lethal inject= ion makes killing as punishment more acceptable to the public. Even when it pre= vents the struggles of the condemned person and avoids maiming the body, it is no different from hanging or shooting as an expression of the absolute power of the state over the helpless individual.

Most people observing an execution= are horrified and disgusted. "I was ashamed," writes sociologist Rich= ard Moran, who witnessed an execution in Texas in 1985. "I was an intruder, the only member of the public who had trespassed on [the condemned man's] private moment of anguish. In my face he could see the horror of his own death."(42) Revulsion at the duty to supervise and witness executions = is one reason why so many prison wardens -- however unsentimental they are abo= ut crime and criminals -- are opponents of capital punishment.

In some people, however, executions seem to appeal to strange, aberrant impulses and give an outlet to sadistic urges. Warden Lewis Lawes wrote of the many req= uests he received to watch electrocutions, and told that when the job of executio= ner became vacant, "I received more than seven hundred applications for the position, many of them offering cut-rate prices."(43)

Public executions were common in t= his country during the 19th century; one of the last was in 1936 in Kentucky, w= hen 20,000 people gathered to watch a young African-American male hanged.(44) Delight in brutality, pain, violence, and death = may always be with us. But surely we must conclude that it is best for the law = not to encourage these impulses. When the government sanctions, commands, and ceremoniously carries out the execution of a prisoner, it lends support to = this destructive side of human nature.

More than two centuries ago, the Italian jurist Cesare Becc= aria, in his highly influential treatise On Crimes and Punishments (1764), assert= ed: "The death penalty cannot be useful, because of the example of barbari= ty it gives men." True, and even if the death penalty were a "useful" deterrent, it would still be an "example of barbarity." No society can safely entrust the enforcement of its laws = to torture, brutality, or killing. Such methods are inherently cruel and will always mock the attempt to cloak them in justice. As Supreme Court Justice Arthur J. Goldberg wrote, "The deliberate institutionalized taking of human life by the state is the greatest conceivable degradation to the dign= ity of the human personality."(45)

Retribution

Justice, it is often insisted, requires the death penalty as the only suitable retribution for heinous crimes. This claim will not bear scrutiny. All punishment by its nature is retributive, not only the death penalty. Whatev= er legitimacy, therefore, is to be found in punishment as just retribution can= in principle be satisfied without recourse to executions.

It is also obvious that the death penalty could be defended on narrowly retributive grounds only for the crim= e of murder, and not for any of the many other crimes that have frequently been = made subject to this mode of punishment (rape, kidnapping, espionage, treason, d= rug kingpins). Few defenders of the death penalty are willing to confine themse= lves consistently to the narrow scope afforded by retribution. In any case, execution is more than a punishment exacted in retribution for the taking o= f a life.

As Camus wrote, "For there to= be equivalence, the death penalty would have to punish a criminal who had warn= ed his victim of the date at which he would inflict a horrible death on him and who, from that moment onward, had confined him at his mercy for months. Suc= h a monster is not encountered in private life."(46)

It is also often argued that death= is what murderers deserve, and that those who oppose the death penalty violate= the fundamental principle that criminals should be punished according to their deserts--"making the punishment fit the crime."

If this principle is understood to require that punishments are unjust unless they are like the crime itself, = then the principle is unacceptable. It would require us to rape rapists, torture torturers, and inflict other horrible and degrading punishment s on offende= rs. It would require us to betray traitors and kill multiple murderers again and again, punishments impossible to inflict. Since we cannot reasonably aim to punish all crimes according to this principle, it is arbitrary to invoke it= as a requirement of justice in the punishment of murderers. =

If, however, the principle of just deserts is understood to require that the severity of punishments must be proportional to the gravity of the crime, and that murder being the gravest crime deserves the severest punishment, then the principle is no doubt soun= d. But it does not compel support for the death penalty. What it does require = is that crimes other than murder be punished with terms of imprisonment or oth= er deprivations less severe than those used in the punishment of murder. =

Criminals no doubt deserve to be punished, and punished with severity appropriate to their culpability and t= he harm they have caused to the innocent. But severity of punishment has its limits -- imposed both by justice and our common human dignity. Governments that respect these limits do not use premeditated, violent homicide as an instrument of social policy.

Some whose loved one was a murder victim believe that they cannot rest until the murderer is executed. But th= e feeling is by no means universal. Coretta Scott King has observed, "As one who= se husband and mother-in-law have died the victims of murder assassination, I stand firmly and unequivocally opposed to the death penalty for those convi= cted of capital offenses. An evil deed is not redeemed by an evil deed of retaliation. Justice is never advanced in the tacking of a human life. Mora= lity is never upheld by a legalized murder."(47)

Kerry Kennedy, daughter of the sla= in Senator Robert Kennedy, has written: "I was eight years old when my fa= ther was murdered. It is almost impossible to describe the pain of losing a pare= nt to a senseless murder.... But even as a child one thing was clear to me: I didn't want the killer, in turn, to be killed. I remember lying in bed and = praying, 'Please, God. Please don't take his life, too.' I saw nothing that could be accomplished in the loss of one life being answered with the loss of anothe= r. And I knew, far too vividly, the anguish that would spread through another family -- another set of parents, children, brothers, and sisters thrown in= to grief."(48)

Financial Costs

It is sometimes suggested that abolishing capital punishment is unfair to the taxpayer, as though life imprisonment were obviously more expensive than executions. If one takes into account all the relevant costs, the reverse is true. "The death penalty is not now, nor has it ever been, a more economical alternative to life imprisonment."(49)

A murder trial normally takes much longer when the death penalty is at issue than when it is not. Litigation c= osts - including the time of judges, prosecutors,public defenders, and court reporters, and the= high costs of briefs -- are all borne by the taxpayer.

A 1982 study showed that were the death penalty to be reintroduced in New York, the cost of the capital trial alone would be more than double the cost of a life term in prison.(50)

In Maryland, a comparison of capit= al trial costs with and without the death penalty for the years 1979-1984 concluded that a death penalty case costs "approximately 42 percent mo= re than a case resulting in a non-death sentence."(51) In 1988 and 1989 <= span class=3DSpellE>th e Kansas legislature voted against reinstating the= death penalty after it was informed that reintroduction would involve a first-year cost of "more than $ 11 million."(52) Florida, with one of the nation's largest death rows, has estimated that the true cost of each execu= tion is approximately $3.2 million, or approximately six times the cost of a life-imprisonment sentence.(53)

The only way to make the death pen= alty a "better buy" than imprisonment is to weaken due process and cur= tail appellate review, which are the defendant's (and society's) only protections against the grossest miscarriages of justice. The savings in dollar s would= be at the cost of justice: In nearly half of the death-penalty cases given rev= iew under federal habeas corpus, the conviction is overturned.(54) <= /span>

Public Opinion

The media commonly report that the American public overwhelmingly supports the death penalty. More careful analysis of public attitudes, however, reveals = that most Americans would oppose the death penalty if convicted murderers were sentenced to life without parole and were required to make some form of financial restitution. In California, for example, a Field Institute survey showed that in 1990,82 percent approved in princ= iple of the death penalty. But when asked to choose between the death penalty and life imprisonment plus restitution, only a small minority--26 percent--continued to favor executions.(53)

A comparable change in attitude to= ward the death penally has been verified in many oth= er states and contradicted in none.

Abolition Trends

The death penalty in the United States needs to be put into international perspective. In 1962, it was reported to the Council of Europe that "t= he facts clearly show that the death penalty is regarded in Europe as somethin= g of an anachronism...."(56)

Today, 28 European countries have abolished the death penalty either in law or in practice. In Great Britain,= it was abolished (except for treason) in 1971; France abolished it in 1981. Ca= nada abolished it in 1976. The United Nations General Assembly affirmed in a for= mal resolution that, throughout the world, it is desirable to "progressive= ly restrict the number of offenses for which the death penalty might be impose= d, with a view to the desirability of abolishing this punishment."(57)

Conspicuous by their indifference = to these recommendations are nations generally known for their disregard for t= he human rights of their citizens: China, Iraq, Iran, South Africa, and the fo= rmer Soviet Union.(58) Americans ought to be embarrassed to find themselves link= ed with the governments of such nations in retaining execution as a method of crime control.

Opposition to the death penalty in= the United States is widespread and diverse. Catholic, Jewish, and Protestant religious groups, national organizations representing people of color, and public-interest law groups are among the more than fifty national organizat= ions that constitute the National Coalition to Abolish the Death Penalty. <= /o:p>

Once in use everywhere and for a w= ide variety of crimes, the death penalty today is generally forbidden by law and widely abandoned in practice. The unmistakable worldwide trend is toward the complete abolition of capital punishment.

For Further Information & Reference

Additional copies of this pamphlet, as well as resource materials such as newsletters, books, legal and legislative information, death-row census, reprinted artic= les, bibliographies, and referrals to other national and state-wide anti-death penalty groups may be obtained from the Capital Punishment Project, American Civil Liberties Union, 122 Maryland Avenue N.E., Washington, D.C., 20002. <= span class=3DSpellE>Diann Y. Rust-Tierney, Esq., is the project's directo= r. The National Coalition to Abolish the Death Penalty, which coordinates the work= of a wide variety of organizations opposed to capital punishment, is located at 1325 G St. N.W. Lower Level B, Washington, D.C., 20005. <= /p>

No one volume on the death penalty currently serves as an up-to-date source book on all aspects of the subject. The Death Penalty in America, 3rd ed., ed. Hugo Adam B= edau, Oxford University Press, 1982, is still useful, and a new edition is in preparation. Many other recent volumes contain valuable information and argument, including: Welsh S. White, The Death Penalty in the Nineties, University of Michigan Press,1991; Samuel R. Gross and Robert Mauro, Death = and Discrimination, Northeastern University Press, 1989; Michael L. Radelet, ed., Facing the Death Penalty, Temple Univer= sity Press, 1989; Kenneth C. Haas and James A. Inciardi, eds., Challenging Capital Punishment, Sage Publications, 1988; United State= s of America -- The Death Penalty, Amnesty International Publications, 1987; Franklin E. Zimring and Gordon Hawkins, Capital Punishment and the American Agenda, Cambridge University Press, 1986; Willi= am J. Bowers, Legal Homicide: Death as Punishment in America, 1864-1982, Northeastern University Press , 1984; Charles L. Black, Jr., Capital Punish= ment, 2nd ed., W. W. Norton, 1981. The wealth of scholarly literature up through = 1988 can be traced with the help of Capital Punishment in America: An Annotated Bibliography, Garland Publishing, 1988, edited by Michael L. Radelet and Margaret Vandiver.

Four more specialized volumes dese= rve mention as well: Michael L. Radelet, Hugo Adam = Bedau, and Constance E. Putnam, In Spite of Innocence: Erroneous Convictions in Capital Cases, Northeastern University Press, 1992; Robert M. Bohm, ed., The Death Penalty in Ameri= ca: Current Research. Anderson Publishing Co., 1991: Victor T. Streib, Death Penalty for Juveniles, Indiana University Press, 1987; and Louis P. <= span class=3DSpellE>Masur, Rites of Execution: Capital Punishment and the Transformation of American Culture, 1776-1865 , Oxford University Press, 19= 89.

Several scholarly and legal journa= ls have devoted whole issues to various legal, sociological, and historical aspects of the problem of the death penalty, notably Dickinson Law Review, = vol. 95, no. 4, Summer 1991; New York University Review of Law & Social Chan= ge, vol. 18, nos. 2 and 3, 1990-1991; Albany Law Review, vol. 54, nos. 3/4, 199= 0; Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, vol. 23, no. 1, November 1989; Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice, vol. 5, no. 4, December 1989; Law and Human Behavior, vol. 8, nos. 1/2, June 1984; U.C. Davis Law Review, vol. 18, no. = 4, summer 1985; Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology. vol. 74, no. 3, fall 1983.

Among the recent U.S. government publications containing information of general interest are: "The Fede= ral Death Penalty Act of 1989," Report of the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 101st Congress, 1st Session, October 1989; "Death Penalty," Hearings Before Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate, 101= st Congress, 1st Session, September-October 1989; "Establishing Constitutional Procedures for the Imposition of Capital Punishment," Report of the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 99th Congress, 2d Session, April 1986; "Capital Punishment," Hearings Before Subcommittee on= Criminal Justice, U.S. House of Representatives, 99th Congress, 1st and 2d Sessions, November 1985-July 1986; "Death Penalty Legislation," hearing Bef= ore the Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate, 99th Congress, 1st Session, September 1985. For earlier federal government publications, see the bibliography by Radelet and Vandiver, pp. 219-20.

Statistical information on death sentences and executions since 1930 may be obtained in the U.S. Bureau of Justice Statistics Bulletin, Capital Punishment, an annual report appearing under various titles since the 1950s. The NAACP Leg= al Defense and Educational Fund publishes "Death Row, U.S.A.," issued since the 1970s several times a year; it reports current demographic information on executions and the death row population. <= /p>

Notes

1.      =   See U.S. Dept. Justice, Capital Punishment, annually, 1980 et seq.

2.      =   See Uniform Crime Reports, annua= lly, 1980 et seq.

3.      =   See Uniform Crime Reports. =

4.      =   Uniform Crime Reports, annually, 1980-1989.

5.      =   Bowers and Pierce, "Deterre= nce or Brutalization," in Crime & Delinquency (1980).

6.      =   U.S. Dept. Justice, Capital Punishment, 1972-1990; Uniform Crime Reports, annually, 1972-1990; and NAACP Legal Defense and Educational Fund, "Death Row, USA," Spring 1992.

7.      =   Bailey and Peterson, in Criminol= ogy (1987), p. 22.

8.      =   Sourcebook of Criminal Justice Statistics -- 1990.

9.      =   Bureau of Justice Statistics, Prisons and Prisoners in the United States (1992), p. 1. =

10.     Wolfson, in Bedau, ed., The Death P= enalty in America, 3rd ed. (1982), p. 167

11.     Ehrlich, in American Economic Review (1974); Phillips, in American Journal of Sociology (1980); and Layson, in Southern Economic Journal (1985)

12.     Lempert, in Crime & Delinquency (1983); Peterson and Bailey= in Chambliss, ed., Criminal Law in Action, 2nd ed. (1984); Bowers, in Hasse and Inciardi, eds., Challenging Capital Punishment (1988); Peterson and Cello, in Social Forces (1988); and Fox and Radelet, in Loyola of Los A= ngeles Law Review (1989).

13.     Blumstein, Cohen, and Nagin,= eds., Deterrence and Incapacitation (1975), p. 358.

14.     West, Solomon, and Diamond, in Beda= u and Pierce, eds., Capital Punishment in the United States (1976).

15.     Bedau, "Recidivism, Parole, and Deterrence," in Bedau, ed., Death Penalty in America, 3rd ed.

16.     Marquart and Sorensen, in Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review (1989= ).

17.     U.S. Bureau of Justice Statistics, "Capital Punishment," 1977, and NAACP LDF, "Death Row, USA," Spring 1= 992.

18.     Bowers, Legal Homicide (1984); Stre= ib, Death Penalty for Juveniles (1987).

19.     "Death Row, USA," 1976 et seq.

20.     Uniform Crime Reports, 1972-1990.

21.     Baldus, Woodworth, and Pulaski, Equal Justice and The Death Penalty (1990), p. 401.

22.     U.S. General Accounting Office, "Death Penalty Sentencing" (1990), pp.5, 6.

23.     "Death Row, USA," Spring 1992; and Sourcebook of Criminal Justice Statistics -- 1990.

24.     U.S. Bureau of Justice Statistics, "Capital Punishment," 1980-1990.

25.     Uniform Crime Reports, 1980-1990.

26.     Memorandum, National Coalition to Abolish the Death Pena= lty, January 1991.

27.     U.S. Bureau of Justice Statistics, "Capital Punishment," 1979; NAACP LDF, "Death Row, USA," Spring 1992.=

28.     Tabak, in Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review (1989).

29.     Gross and Mauro, Death and Discrimination (1989), p. 224= .

30.     Black, Capital Punishment. The Inevitability of Caprice = and Mistake. 2nd ed. (1982).

31.     Lucas Recueil des debats ... (1831) pt. II, p. 32.

32.     Radelet, Bedau, and Putnam, In Spit= e of Innocence (1992); Bedau and Radelet, Miscarriages of Justice in Potentially Capital Cases, Stanford Law Review (1987).

33.     Miller, Invitation to a Lynching (1975); also The New Yo= rk Times, Sept 10, 1975, p.1.

34.     "Capital Punishment" Senate Hearings (1981) pp. 713-20

35.     Atlanta Weekly, May 30, 1982.

36.     Adams, Hoffer, and Hoffer, Adams v. Texas (1991).

37.     Davies, White Lies (1991).

38.     Glass v. Louisiana, 471 U.S. 1080 (1985).

39.     Boston Globe, April 24, 1983, p. 24. <= /p>

40.     The New York Times, December 14, 1988, p. A29.

41.     Ibid.

42.     Los Angeles Times, March 24, 1985, Pt IV, p. 5.

43.     Lawes, Life and Death in Sing Sing (1928).

44.     Teeters, in Journal of the Lancaster County Historical Society (1960).

45.     Boston Globe, August 16, 1976, p. 17 <= /p>

46.     Camus, "Reflections on the Guillotine," in Resistance, Rebellion and Death (1960).

47.     Speech to National Coalition to Abolish the Death Penalt= y, Washington, D.C., September 26, 1981.

48.     Foreword to Gray and Stanley, A Punishment in Search of A Crime (1989).

49.     Spangenberg and Walsh, in Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review (1989), = p. 47

50.     N. Y. State Defenders Assn., Capital Losses (1982).

51.     U S. Govt. Accounting Office, Limited Data Available on Costs of Death Sentences (1989), p. 50.

52.     Cited in Spangenberg and Wal= sh, note 49.

53.     Miami Herald, July 10, 1988.

54.     New York Times, Sept. 22, 1989

55.     New York Times, May 28, 1990; and Fox, Radelet, and Bonsteel, in N.Y.U. Review of Law and Social Change (1990-91).

56.     Ancel, The Death Penalty in Europe= an Countries (1962), p 55.

57.     UN, Ecosoc, Official Records= 58th Sess. (1971), Supl. 1, p.36. =

58.     Hood, The Death Penalty: A World-Wide Perspective (1989); Amnesty International, When The State Kills... (1989).


Revised July 1992. =

 

------=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910 Content-Location: file:///C:/D1123EF9/Bedau--TheCaseAgainsttheDeathPenalty_files/themedata.thmx Content-Transfer-Encoding: base64 Content-Type: application/vnd.ms-officetheme UEsDBBQABgAIAAAAIQCCirwT+gAAABwCAAATAAAAW0NvbnRlbnRfVHlwZXNdLnhtbKyRy2rDMBBF 94X+g9C22HK6KKXYzqJJd30s0g8Y5LEtao+ENAnJ33fsuFC6CC10IxBizpl7Va6P46AOGJPzVOlV XmiFZH3jqKv0++4pu9cqMVADgyes9AmTXtfXV+XuFDApmaZU6Z45PBiTbI8jpNwHJHlpfRyB5Ro7 E8B+QIfmtijujPXESJzxxNB1+SoLRNegeoPILzCKx7Cg8Pv5DCSAmAtYq8czYVqi0hDC4CywRDAH an7oM9+2zmLj7X4UaT6DF9jNBDO/XGD1P+ov5wZb2A+stkfp4lx/xCH9LdtSay6Tc/7Uu5AuGC6X t7Rh5r+tPwEAAP//AwBQSwMEFAAGAAgAAAAhAKXWp+fAAAAANgEAAAsAAABfcmVscy8ucmVsc4SP z2rDMAyH74W9g9F9UdLDGCV2L6WQQy+jfQDhKH9oIhvbG+vbT8cGCrsIhKTv96k9/q6L+eGU5yAW mqoGw+JDP8to4XY9v3+CyYWkpyUIW3hwhqN727VfvFDRozzNMRulSLYwlRIPiNlPvFKuQmTRyRDS SkXbNGIkf6eRcV/XH5ieGeA2TNP1FlLXN2Cuj6jJ/7PDMMyeT8F/ryzlRQRuN5RMaeRioagv41O9 kKhlqtQe0LW4+db9AQAA//8DAFBLAwQUAAYACAAAACEAa3mWFoMAAACKAAAAHAAAAHRoZW1lL3Ro ZW1lL3RoZW1lTWFuYWdlci54bWwMzE0KwyAQQOF9oXeQ2TdjuyhFYrLLrrv2AEOcGkHHoNKf29fl 44M3zt8U1ZtLDVksnAcNimXNLoi38Hwspxuo2kgcxSxs4ccV5ul4GMm0jRPfSchzUX0j1ZCFrbXd INa1K9Uh7yzdXrkkaj2LR1fo0/cp4kXrKyYKAjj9AQAA//8DAFBLAwQUAAYACAAAACEAlrWt4pYG AABQGwAAFgAAAHRoZW1lL3RoZW1lL3RoZW1lMS54bWzsWU9v2zYUvw/YdyB0b2MndhoHdYrYsZst TRvEboceaYmW2FCiQNJJfRva44ABw7phhxXYbYdhW4EW2KX7NNk6bB3Qr7BHUpLFWF6SNtiKrT4k Evnj+/8eH6mr1+7HDB0SISlP2l79cs1DJPF5QJOw7d0e9i+teUgqnASY8YS0vSmR3rWN99+7itdV RGKCYH0i13Hbi5RK15eWpA/DWF7mKUlgbsxFjBW8inApEPgI6MZsablWW12KMU08lOAYyN4aj6lP 0FCT9DZy4j0Gr4mSesBnYqBJE2eFwQYHdY2QU9llAh1i1vaAT8CPhuS+8hDDUsFE26uZn7e0cXUJ r2eLmFqwtrSub37ZumxBcLBseIpwVDCt9xutK1sFfQNgah7X6/W6vXpBzwCw74OmVpYyzUZ/rd7J aZZA9nGedrfWrDVcfIn+ypzMrU6n02xlsliiBmQfG3P4tdpqY3PZwRuQxTfn8I3OZre76uANyOJX 5/D9K63Vhos3oIjR5GAOrR3a72fUC8iYs+1K+BrA12oZfIaCaCiiS7MY80QtirUY3+OiDwANZFjR BKlpSsbYhyju4ngkKNYM8DrBpRk75Mu5Ic0LSV/QVLW9D1MMGTGj9+r596+eP0XHD54dP/jp+OHD 4wc/WkLOqm2chOVVL7/97M/HH6M/nn7z8tEX1XhZxv/6wye//Px5NRDSZybOiy+f/PbsyYuvPv39 u0cV8E2BR2X4kMZEopvkCO3zGBQzVnElJyNxvhXDCNPyis0klDjBmksF/Z6KHPTNKWaZdxw5OsS1 4B0B5aMKeH1yzxF4EImJohWcd6LYAe5yzjpcVFphR/MqmXk4ScJq5mJSxu1jfFjFu4sTx7+9SQp1 Mw9LR/FuRBwx9xhOFA5JQhTSc/yAkArt7lLq2HWX+oJLPlboLkUdTCtNMqQjJ5pmi7ZpDH6ZVukM /nZss3sHdTir0nqLHLpIyArMKoQfEuaY8TqeKBxXkRzimJUNfgOrqErIwVT4ZVxPKvB0SBhHvYBI WbXmlgB9S07fwVCxKt2+y6axixSKHlTRvIE5LyO3+EE3wnFahR3QJCpjP5AHEKIY7XFVBd/lbobo d/ADTha6+w4ljrtPrwa3aeiINAsQPTMR2pdQqp0KHNPk78oxo1CPbQxcXDmGAvji68cVkfW2FuJN 2JOqMmH7RPldhDtZdLtcBPTtr7lbeJLsEQjz+Y3nXcl9V3K9/3zJXZTPZy20s9oKZVf3DbYpNi1y vLBDHlPGBmrKyA1pmmQJ+0TQh0G9zpwOSXFiSiN4zOq6gwsFNmuQ4OojqqJBhFNosOueJhLKjHQo UcolHOzMcCVtjYcmXdljYVMfGGw9kFjt8sAOr+jh/FxQkDG7TWgOnzmjFU3grMxWrmREQe3XYVbX Qp2ZW92IZkqdw61QGXw4rxoMFtaEBgRB2wJWXoXzuWYNBxPMSKDtbvfe3C3GCxfpIhnhgGQ+0nrP +6hunJTHirkJgNip8JE+5J1itRK3lib7BtzO4qQyu8YCdrn33sRLeQTPvKTz9kQ6sqScnCxBR22v 1VxuesjHadsbw5kWHuMUvC51z4dZCBdDvhI27E9NZpPlM2+2csXcJKjDNYW1+5zCTh1IhVRbWEY2 NMxUFgIs0Zys/MtNMOtFKWAj/TWkWFmDYPjXpAA7uq4l4zHxVdnZpRFtO/ualVI+UUQMouAIjdhE 7GNwvw5V0CegEq4mTEXQL3CPpq1tptzinCVd+fbK4Ow4ZmmEs3KrUzTPZAs3eVzIYN5K4oFulbIb 5c6vikn5C1KlHMb/M1X0fgI3BSuB9oAP17gCI52vbY8LFXGoQmlE/b6AxsHUDogWuIuFaQgquEw2 /wU51P9tzlkaJq3hwKf2aYgEhf1IRYKQPShLJvpOIVbP9i5LkmWETESVxJWpFXtEDgkb6hq4qvd2 D0UQ6qaaZGXA4E7Gn/ueZdAo1E1OOd+cGlLsvTYH/unOxyYzKOXWYdPQ5PYvRKzYVe16szzfe8uK 6IlZm9XIswKYlbaCVpb2rynCObdaW7HmNF5u5sKBF+c1hsGiIUrhvgfpP7D/UeEz+2VCb6hDvg+1 FcGHBk0Mwgai+pJtPJAukHZwBI2THbTBpElZ02atk7ZavllfcKdb8D1hbC3ZWfx9TmMXzZnLzsnF izR2ZmHH1nZsoanBsydTFIbG+UHGOMZ80ip/deKje+DoLbjfnzAlTTDBNyWBofUcmDyA5LcczdKN vwAAAP//AwBQSwMEFAAGAAgAAAAhAA3RkJ+2AAAAGwEAACcAAAB0aGVtZS90aGVtZS9fcmVscy90 aGVtZU1hbmFnZXIueG1sLnJlbHOEj00KwjAUhPeCdwhvb9O6EJEm3YjQrdQDhOQ1DTY/JFHs7Q2u LAguh2G+mWm7l53JE2My3jFoqhoIOumVcZrBbbjsjkBSFk6J2TtksGCCjm837RVnkUsoTSYkUigu MZhyDidKk5zQilT5gK44o49W5CKjpkHIu9BI93V9oPGbAXzFJL1iEHvVABmWUJr/s/04GolnLx8W Xf5RQXPZhQUoosbM4CObqkwEylu6usTfAAAA//8DAFBLAQItABQABgAIAAAAIQCCirwT+gAAABwC AAATAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAABbQ29udGVudF9UeXBlc10ueG1sUEsBAi0AFAAGAAgAAAAhAKXW p+fAAAAANgEAAAsAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAKwEAAF9yZWxzLy5yZWxzUEsBAi0AFAAGAAgAAAAhAGt5 lhaDAAAAigAAABwAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAFAIAAHRoZW1lL3RoZW1lL3RoZW1lTWFuYWdlci54bWxQ SwECLQAUAAYACAAAACEAlrWt4pYGAABQGwAAFgAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAADRAgAAdGhlbWUvdGhlbWUv dGhlbWUxLnhtbFBLAQItABQABgAIAAAAIQAN0ZCftgAAABsBAAAnAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAJsJAAB0 aGVtZS90aGVtZS9fcmVscy90aGVtZU1hbmFnZXIueG1sLnJlbHNQSwUGAAAAAAUABQBdAQAAlgoA AAAA ------=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910 Content-Location: file:///C:/D1123EF9/Bedau--TheCaseAgainsttheDeathPenalty_files/colorschememapping.xml Content-Transfer-Encoding: quoted-printable Content-Type: text/xml ------=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910 Content-Location: file:///C:/D1123EF9/Bedau--TheCaseAgainsttheDeathPenalty_files/image001.jpg Content-Transfer-Encoding: base64 Content-Type: image/jpeg /9j/4AAQSkZJRgABAQEASwBLAAD/4wMOTVNPIFBhbGV0dGUg+uzP++3R++7S++/W/O7S/O/S/PDV /PDY/PHV/e/S/e/W/fHZ/fLZ/fLc/fPc/vDV/vHW/vHZ/vLY/vLa/vLc/vPe/vTf/vXe/vXg/vXi /vbh/vbk/vfl/vjo//Pb//Xh+OrO+ezO+ezQ+ezS+e7V+urN+uvP+u3P+u3S+u3U+u3V+u/W++zN ++zP++zQ++zR++3P++3S++3T++7Q++7R++7T++7U++7V++/R++/T++/V++/Y+/DX+/Da+/HW+/Ha +/Hb+/Lc/OvO/O3O/O3Q/O3R/O7P/O7R/O7T/O7U/O7W/O/T/O/U/O/V/O/W/O/X/PDU/PDW/PDX /PDZ/PDa/PHU/PHW/PHY/PHZ/PHa/PHb/PHc/PLW/PLb/PPc/PPd/PPe/PTf/PTg/PTi/ezN/e3O /e3P/e3R/e7P/e7Q/e7R/e7S/e/O/e/Q/e/R/e/T/e/U/e/V/e/X/fDP/fDS/fDT/fDU/fDV/fDW /fDX/fDY/fDZ/fHT/fHU/fHV/fHW/fHX/fHY/fHa/fHb/fLV/fLX/fLY/fLa/fLb/fLd/fPZ/fPa /fPb/fPd/fPe/fTd/fXh/fXk/fbk/ffk/u/Q/u/S/u/U/u/V/vDS/vDT/vDU/vDW/vDX/vDY/vHT /vHU/vHV/vHX/vHY/vHa/vHb/vLV/vLW/vLX/vLZ/vLb/vLd/vPW/vPY/vPZ/vPa/vPb/vPc/vPd /vPf/vTZ/vTa/vTb/vTc/vTd/vTe/vTg/vTh/vXd/vXf/vXh/vXj/vbg/vbi/vbj/vfk/vfn/vjk /vjm/vnp/vnr//DT//HW//HY//LV//LX//LY//LZ//La//Lb//Lc//PW//PX//PY//PZ//Pa//Pc //Pd//Pe//TY//Ta//Tb//Tc//Td//Te//Tf//Tg//Th//Xb//Xc//Xd//Xe//Xf//Xg//Xi//Xj //be//bf//bg//bh//bi//bj//bk//bl//fh//fj//fk//fl//fm//fn//jm//jn//jo//jp//jq //nm//np/9sAQwALCAgKCAcLCgkKDQwLDREcEhEPDxEiGRoUHCkkKyooJCcnLTJANy0wPTAnJzhM OT1DRUhJSCs2T1VORlRAR0hF/9sAQwEMDQ0RDxEhEhIhRS4nLkVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVF RUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVFRUVF/8AAEQgAgACAAwEiAAIRAQMRAf/EABgAAQEB AQEAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAEAAgMH/8QAIRAAAwACAgMBAQEBAAAAAAAAAAERITECQRJRcWGBkaH/xAAY AQEBAAMAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAQIDBP/EABgRAQEBAQEAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAARASEx/9oADAMBAAIR AxEAPwD1RtozXSdJHK3Gk+TmCGUDNYvomiz6AkqtlP0ksDM/oRpP2TyZbBci0ifsG8jyeARFatRK 6BZGoqKEOy0sAL40PBFfTBv6mXgGvErgGS2Yq1gGUyIDASHoUWIw10Hj6OnJqHOjQrhjYqWGU2mb bwBlkX9HCIoRpNf0yyTxoYiThPLwCybSQwY+ho24vpmZCpM1/wBMzMJYAXnAWaNM5vY0dE/IJWZ4 t02kXETWWEybgWCDOguTYTJIB+0TUz2L99BydAJk0gWXspGUK2aiCLYPkPBctlV0VuzMzgDbwsA1 bQX00tAYxTdMyPCIBT9jyMdmuPoUPETPxFYShfZjxzk0m6Tieyik2L2VwC5VaAFZBfHItt4QZgFG M/DOkHk6Bp+yseQoteWQJ8jCdZvirxjLwmhKM8kMxk00YSzGIFOKk0n9NzBlv0IKYDeEwTfZpKbI MitwZgkuxA6Bt/0ny/MisooxaTzk14rsmlNiAn+i+WIgewzYArZrIJNC1OwBPJJ4/RqsB8f8Azlv 8FOBHMCuiBwVB6J1pQCTZvaKJmeWGXwTVYGrUCAZ7ZnbyLYdgTo8emW1CeHgDVTJmF7NJvXZaKJ/ Sju8GeWBXJT9ILkuw8YTZeXoCaFYToI1KAuMzjka+7Mv8GikDqwuzaWBByWWdFEgiuhqGCSxTLb2 jfkjLWYi6LyXoL2XgTXonRN0koA7IJ4+sNI34g+OCwrK2dFg51p4NVwYa//Z ------=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910 Content-Location: file:///C:/D1123EF9/Bedau--TheCaseAgainsttheDeathPenalty_files/filelist.xml Content-Transfer-Encoding: quoted-printable Content-Type: text/xml; charset="utf-8" ------=_NextPart_01CA9E92.C2E8C910--