The Self as a Center of Narrative
Gravity
By Daniel C. Dennett
(Danish
translation, "Selvet som
fortællingens tyngdepunkt,"
Philosophia, 15, 275-88, 1986.)
What
is a self? I will try to answer this question by developing an analogy with something
much simpler, something which is nowhere near as puzzling as a self, but has
some properties in common with selves.
What
I have in mind is the center of gravity of an
object.
This
is a well-behaved concept in Newtonian physics. But a center of gravity is
not an atom or a subatomic particle or any other physical item in the world.
It has no mass; it has no color; it has no physical properties at all, except
for spatio-temporal location. It is a fine example
of what Hans Reichenbach would call an abstractum. It is a purely abstract object. It is,
if you like , a theorist's fiction. It is not one of
the real things in the universe in addition to the atoms. But it is a fiction
that has nicely defined, well delineated and well behaved role within
physics.
Let
me remind you how robust and familiar the idea of a center of gravity is.
Consider a chair. Like all other physical objects, it has a center of
gravity. If you start tipping it, you can tell more or less accurately
whether it would start to fall over or fall back in place if you let go of
it. We're all quite good at making predictions involving centers of gravity
and devising explanations about when and why things fall over. Place a book
on the chair. It, too, has a center of gravity. If you start to push it over
the edge, we know that at some point will fall. It will fall when its center
of gravity is no longer directly over a point of its supporting base (the
chair seat). Notice that that statement is itself virtually tautological. The
key terms in it are all interdefinable. And yet it
can also figure in explanations that appear to be causal explanations of some
sort. We ask "Why doesn't that lamp tip over?" We reply
"Because its center of gravity is so low." Is this a causal
explanation? It can compete with explanations that are clearly causal, such
as: "Because it's nailed to the table," and "Because it's
supported by wires."
We
can manipulate centers of gravity. For instance, I change the center of
gravity of a water pitcher easily, by pouring some of the water out. So,
although a center of gravity is a purely abstract object, it has a spatio-temporal career, which I can affect by my actions.
It has a history, but its history can include some rather strange episodes.
Although it moves around in space and time, its motion can be discontinuous.
For instance, if I were to take a piece of bubble gum and suddenly stick it
on the pitcher's handle, that would shift the
pitcher's center of gravity from point A to point B. But the center of
gravity would not have to move through all the intervening positions. As an abstractum, it is not bound by all the constraints of
physical travel.
Consider
the center of gravity of a slightly more complicated object. Suppose we
wanted to keep track of the career of the center of gravity of some complex
machine with lots of turning gears and camshafts and reciprocating rods--the
engine of a steam-powered unicycle, perhaps. And suppose our theory of the
machine's operation permitted us to plot the complicated trajectory of the
center of gravity precisely. And suppose--most improbably--that we discovered
that in this particular machine the trajectory of the center of gravity was
precisely the same as the trajectory of a particular iron atom in the
crankshaft. Even if this were discovered, we would be wrong even to entertain
the hypothesis that the machine's center of gravity was (identical with) that
iron atom. That would be a category mistake. A center of gravity is just
an abstractum. It's just a fictional object. But
when I say it's a fictional object, I do not mean to disparage it; it's a
wonderful fictional object, and it has a perfectly legitimate place within
serious, sober, echt physical science.
A
self is also an abstract object, a theorist's fiction. The theory is not
particle physics but what we might call a branch of people-physics; it is
more soberly known as a phenomenology or hermeneutics, or soul-science (Geisteswissenschaft). The physicist does an interpretation,
if you like, of the chair and its behavior, and comes up with the theoretical
abstraction of a center of gravity, which is then very useful in
characterizing the behaviour of the chair in the
future, under a wide variety of conditions. The hermeneuticist
or phenomenologist--or anthropologist--sees some rather more complicated
things moving about in the world--human beings and animals--and is faced with
a similar problem of interpretation. It turns out to be theoretically
perspicuous to organize the interpretation around a central abstraction: each
person has a self (in addition to a center of gravity). In fact we
have to posit selves for ourselves as well. The theoretical problem of
self-interpretation is at least as difficult and important as the problem of
other-interpretation.
Now
how does a self differ from a center of gravity? It is a much more
complicated concept. I will try to elucidate it via an analogy with another
sort of fictional object: fictional characters in literature. Pick up Moby
Dick and open it up to page one. It says, "Call me Ishmael."
Call whom Ishmael? Call Melville Ishmael? No. Call Ishmael Ishmael. Melville has created a fictional character named
Ishmael. As you read the book you learn about Ishmael, about his life, about
his beliefs and desires, his acts and attitudes. You learn a lot more about
Ishmael then Melville ever explicitly tells you. Some of it you can read in
by implication. Some of it you can read in by extrapolation. But beyond the
limits of such extrapolation fictional worlds are simply indeterminate.
Thus, consider the following question (borrowed from David Lewis's
"Truth and Fiction," American Philosophical Quarterly, 1978,
15, pp.37-46). Did Sherlock
Holmes have three nostrils? The answer of course is no, but not because Conan
Doyle ever says that he doesn't, or that he has two, but because we're
entitled to make that extrapolation. In the absence of evidence to the
contrary, Sherlock Holmes' nose can be supposed to be normal. Another
question: Did Sherlock Holmes have a mole on his left shoulder blade? The
answer to this question is neither yes nor no. Nothing about the text or
about the principles of extrapolation from the text permit
an answer to that question. There is simply no fact of the matter. Why?
Because Sherlock Holmes is a merely fictional character, created by, or
constituted out of, the text and the culture in which that text resides.
This
indeterminacy is a fundamental property of fictional objects which strongly
distinguishes them from another sort of object scientists talk about:
theoretical entities, or what Reichenbach called illata--inferred entities, such as atoms,
molecules and neutrinos. A logician might say that the "principle of
bivalence" does not hold for fictional objects. That is to say, with
regard to any actual man, living or dead, the question of whether or not he
has or had a mole on his left shoulder blade has an answer, yes or no. Did
Aristotle has such a mole? There is a fact of the
matter even if we can never discover it. But with regard to a fictional
character, that question may have no answer at all.
We
can imagine someone, a benighted literary critic, perhaps, who doesn't
understand that fiction is fiction. This critic has a strange theory about
how fiction works. He thinks that something literally magical happens when a
novelist writes a novel. When a novelist sets down words on paper, this
critic says (one often hears claims like this, but not meant to be taken
completely literally), the novelist actually creates a world.
A litmus test for this bizarre view is the principle of bivalence: when our
imagined critic speaks of a fictional world he means a strange sort of real
world, a world in which the principle of bivalence holds. Such a critic might
seriously wonder whether Dr Watson was really Moriarty's second
cousin, or whether the conductor of the train that took Holmes and Watson to Aldershot was also the conductor of the train that
brought them back to London.
That sort of question can't properly arise if you understand fiction
correctly, of course. Whereas analogous questions about historical personages
have to have yes or no answers, even if we may never be able to dredge them
up.
Centers
of gravity, as a fictional objects, exhibit the same
feature. They have only the properties that the theory that constitutes them
endowed them with. If you scratch your head and say, "I wonder if maybe
centers of gravity are really neutrinos!" you have misunderstood the
theoretical status of a center of gravity.
Now
how can I make the claim that a self--your own real self, for instance--is
rather like a fictional character? Aren't all fictional selves
dependent for their very creation on the existence of real selves? It
may seem so, but I will argue that this is an illusion. Let's go back to
Ishmael. Ishmael is a fictional character, although we can certainly learn
all about him. One might find him in many regards more real than many of
one's friends. But, one thinks, Ishmael was created by Melville, and Melville
is a real character--was a real character. A real self. Doesn't this show
that it takes a real self to create a fictional self? I think not, but If I
am to convince you, I must push you through an exercise of the imagination.
First
of all, I want to imagine something some of you may think incredible: a
novel-writing machine. We can suppose it is a product of artificial
intelligence research, a computer that has been designed or programmed to
write novels. But it has not been designed to write any particular novel. We
can suppose (if it helps) that it has been given a great stock of whatever
information it might need, and some partially random and hence unpredictable
ways of starting the seed of a story going, and building upon it. Now imagine
that the designers are sitting back, wondering what kind of novel their
creation is going to write. They turn the thing on and after a while the high
speed printer begins to go clickety-clack and out
comes the first sentence. "Call me Gilbert," it says. What follows
is the apparent autobiography of some fictional Gilbert. Now Gilbert is a
fictional, created self but its creator is no self. Of course there were
human designers who designed the machine, but they didn't design Gilbert.
Gilbert is a product of a design or invention process in which there aren't
any selves at all. That is, I am stipulating that this is not a
conscious machine, not a "thinker." It is a dumb machine, but it
does have the power to write a passable novel. (IF you think this is strictly
impossible I can only challenge you to show why you think this must be so,
and invite you read on; in the end you may not have an interest in defending
such a precarious impossibility-claim.)
So
we are to imagine that a passable story is emitted from the machine. Notice
that we can perform the same sort of literary exegesis with regard to this
novel as we can with any other. In fact if you were to pick up a novel at
random out of a library, you could not tell with certainty that it wasn't
written by something like this machine. (And if you're a New Critic you
shouldn't care.) You've got a text and you can interpret it, and so you can
learn the story, the life and adventures of Gilbert. Your expectations and
predictions, as you read, and your interpretive reconstruction of what you
have already read, will congeal around the central node of the fictional
character, Gilbert.
But
now I want to twiddle the knobs on this thought experiment. So far we've
imagined the novel, The Life and Times of Gilbert,
clanking out of a computer that is just a box, sitting in the corner of some
lab. But now I want to change the story a little bit and suppose that the
computer has arms and legs--or better: wheels. (I don't want to make it too
anthropomorphic.) It has a television eye, and it moves around in the world.
It also begins its tale with "Call me Gilbert," and tells a novel,
but now we notice that if we do the trick that the New Critics say you should
never do, and look outside the text, we discover
that there's a truth-preserving interpretation of that text in the real
world. The adventures of Gilbert, the fictional character, now bear a
striking and presumably non-coincidental relationship to the adventures of
this robot rolling around in the world. If you hit the robot with a baseball
bat, very shortly thereafter the story of Gilbert includes his being hit with
a baseball bat by somebody who looks like you. Every now and then the robot
gets locked in the closed and then says "Help me!" Help whom? Well,
help Gilbert, presumably. But who is Gilbert? Is Gilbert the robot, or merely the fictional self created by the robot?
If we go and help the robot out of the closet, it sends us a note:
"Thank you. Love, Gilbert." At this point we will be unable to
ignore the fact that the fictional career of the fictional Gilbert bears an
interesting resemblance to the "career" of this mere robot moving
through the world. We can still maintain that the robot's brain, the
robot's computer, really knows nothing about the world; it's not a
self. It's just a clanky computer. It doesn't know
what it's doing. It doesn't even know that it's creating a fictional
character. (The same is just as true of your brain; it doesn't know
what it's doing either.) Nevertheless, the patterns in the behavior that is
being controlled by the computer are interpretable, by us, as accreting
biography--telling the narrative of a self. But we are not the only
interpreters. The robot novelist is also, of course, an interpreter: a self-interpreter,
providing its own account of its activities in the world.
I
propose that we take this analogy seriously. "Where is the self?" a
materialist philosopher or neuroscientist might ask. It is a category mistake
to start looking around for the self in the brain. Unlike centers of gravity,
whose sole property is their spatio-temporal
position, selves have a spatio-temporal position
that is only grossly defined. Roughly speaking, in the normal case if there
are three human beings sitting on a park bench, there are three selves there,
all in a row and roughly equidistant from the fountain they face. Or we might
use a rather antique turn of phrase and talk about how many souls are
located in the park. ("All twenty souls in the starboard lifeboat were
saved, but those that remained on deck perished.")
Brain
research may permit us to make some more fine-grained localizations, but the
capacity to achieve some fine-grained localization does not give one
grounds for supposing that the process of localization can continue
indefinitely and that the day will finally come when we can say, "That
cell there, right in the middle of hippocampus (or wherever)--that's the
self!"
There's
a big difference, of course, between fictional characters and our own selves.
One I would stress is that a fictional character is usually encountered as a fait
accompli. After the novel has been written and published, you read it.
At that point it is too late for the novelist to render determinate anything
indeterminate that strikes your curiosity. Dostoevsky is dead; you can't ask
him what else Raskolnikov thought while he
sat in the police station. But novels don't have to be that way. John Updike
has written three novels about Rabbit Angstrom: Rabbit Run, Rabbit
Redux, and Rabbit is Rich.
Suppose that those of us who particularly liked the first novel were to get
together and compose a list of questions for Updike--things we wished Updike
has talked about in that first novel, when Rabbit was a young former
basketball star. We could send our questions to Updike and ask him to
consider writing another novel in the series, only this time not continuing
the chronological sequence. Like Lawrence Durrell's Alexandria Quarter,
the Rabbit series could include another novel about Rabbit's early days when
he was still playing basketball, and this novel could answer our questions.
Notice
what we would not be doing in such a case. We would not be saying to
Updike, "Tell us the answers that you already know, the answers that are
already fixed to those questions. Come on, let us
know all those secrets you've been keeping from us." Nor would we be
asking Updike to do research, as we might ask the author of a multi-volume
biography of a real person, We would be asking him to write a new novel, to
invent some more novel for us, on demand. And if he
acceded, he would enlarge and make more determinate the character of Rabbit
Angstrom in the process of writing the new novel. In this way matters which
are indeterminate at one time can become determined later by a creative step.
I
propose that this imagined exercise with Updike, getting him to write more
novels on demand to answer our questions, is actually a familiar exercise.
That is the way we treat each other; that is the way we are. We cannot undo
those parts of our pasts that are determinate, but our selves are constantly
being made more determinate as we go along in response to the way the world
impinges on us. Of course it is also possible for a person to engage in
auto-hermeneutics, interpretation of one's self, and in particular to go back
and think about one's past, and one's memories, and to rethink them and
rewrite them. This process does change the "fictional" character,
the character that you are, in much the way that Rabbit Angstrom, after
Updike writes the second novel about him as a young man, comes to be a rather
different fictional character, determinate in ways he was never determinate
before. This would be an utterly mysterious and magical prospect (and hence
something no one should take seriously) if the self were
anything but an abstractum.
I
want to bring this out by extracting one more feature from the Updike thought
experiment. Updike might take up our request but then he might prove to be
forgetful. After all, it's been many years since he wrote Rabbit Run.
He might not want to go back and reread it carefully; and when he wrote the
new novel it might end up being inconsistent with the first. He might have
Rabbit being in two places at one time, for instance. If we wanted to settle
what the true story was, we'd be falling into error; there is no true
story. In such a circumstance there would be simply be
a failure of coherence of all the data that we had about Rabbit. And because
Rabbit is a fictional character, we wouldn't smite our foreheads in wonder
and declare "Oh my goodness! There's a rift in the universe; we've found
a contradiction in nature!" Nothing is easier than contradiction when
you're dealing with fiction; a fictional character can have contradictory
properties because it's just a fictional character. We find such
contradictions intolerable, however, when we are trying to interpret
something or someone, even a fictional character, so we typically bifurcate
the character to resolve the conflict.
Something
like this seems to happen to real people on rare occasions. Consider the
putatively true case histories recorded in The Three Faces of Eve and Sybil.
(Corbett H. Thigpen and Hervey Cleckly,
The Three Faces of Eve, McGraw Hill, 1957, and Flora Rheta Schreiber, Sybil, Warner paperback, 1973.)
Eve's three faces were the faces of three distinct personalities, it seems,
and the woman portrayed in Sybil had many different selves, or
so it seems. How can we make sense of this? Here is one way--a solemn,
skeptical way favored by some of the psychotherapists with whom I've talked
about such cases: when Sybil went in to see her therapist the first time, she
wasn't several different people rolled into one body. Sybil was a
novel-writing machine that fell in with a very ingenious questioner, a very
eager reader. And together they collaborated--innocently--to write many, many
chapters of a new novel. And, of course, since Sybil was a sort of living
novel, she went out and engaged in the world with these new selves, more or
less created on demand, under the eager suggestion of a therapist.
I
now believe that this is overly skeptical. The population explosion of new
characters that typically follows the onset of psychotherapy for sufferers of
Multiple Personality Disorder (MPD) is probably to be explained along just
these lines, but there is quite compelling evidence in some cases that some
multiplicity of selves (two or three or four, let us say) had already begun
laying down biography before the therapist came along to do the
"reading". And in any event, Sybil is only a strikingly
pathological case of something quite normal, a behavior pattern we can find
in ourselves. We are all, at times, confabulators, telling and retelling
ourselves the story of our own lives, with scant attention to the question of
truth. Why, though do we behave this way? Why are we all such inveterate and
inventive autobiographical novelists? As Umberto Maturana
has (uncontroversially) observed: "Everything
said is said by a speaker to another speaker that may be himself." But
why should one talk to oneself? Why isn't that an utterly idle activity, as
systematically futile as trying to pick oneself up by one's own bootstraps?
A
central clue comes from the sort of phenomena uncovered by Michael Gazzaniga's research on those rare individuals--the
"split-brain subjects"--whose corpus callosum
has been surgically severed, creating in them two largely independent
cortical hemispheres that can, on occasion, be differently informed about the
current scene. Does the operation split the self in two? After the
operation, patients normally exhibit no signs of psychological splitting,
appearing to be no less unified than you or I except under particularly
contrived circumstances. But on Gazzaniga's view,
this does not so much show that the patients have preserved their
pre-surgical unity as that the unity of normal life is an illusion.
According
to Gazzaniga, the normal mind is not
beautifully unified, but rather a problematically yoked-together bundle of
partly autonomous systems. All parts of the mind are not equally accessible
to each other at all times. These modules or systems sometimes have internal
communication problems which they solve by various ingenious and devious
routes. If this is true (and I think it is), it may provide us with an answer
to a most puzzling question about conscious thought: what good is it? Such a
question begs for a evolutionary answer, but it will
have to speculative, of course. (It is not critical to my speculative answer,
for the moment, where genetic evolution and transmission breaks off and
cultural evolution and transmission takes over.)
In
the beginning--according to Julian Jaynes (The
Origins of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind, Boston:
Houghton Mifflin, 1976), whose account I am adapting--were speakers, our
ancestors, who weren't really conscious. They spoke, but they just sort of
blurted things out, more or less the way bees do bee dances, or the way
computers talk to each other. That is not conscious communication, surely.
When these ancestors had problems, sometimes they would "ask" for
help (more or less like Gilbert saying "Help me!" when he was
locked in the closet), and sometimes there would be somebody around to hear
them. So they got into the habit of asking for assistance and, particularly,
asking questions. Whenever they couldn't figure out how to solve some
problem, they would ask a question, addressed to no one in particular, and
sometimes whoever was standing around could answer them. And they also came
to be designed to be provoked on many such occasions into answering questions
like that--to the best of their ability--when asked.
Then
one day one of our ancestors asked a question in what was apparently an
inappropriate circumstance: there was nobody around to be the audience.
Strangely enough, he heard his own question, and this stimulated him,
cooperatively, to think of an answer, and sure enough the answer came to him.
He had established, without realizing what he had done, a communication link
between two parts of his brain, between which there was, for some deep
biological reason, an accessibility problem. One component of the mind had
confronted a problem that another component could solve; if only the problem
could be posed for the latter component! Thanks to his habit of asking
questions, our ancestor stumbled upon a route via the ears. What a discovery!
Sometimes talking and listening to yourself can have
wonderful effects, not otherwise obtainable. All that is needed to make sense
of this idea is the hypothesis that the modules of the mind have different
capacities and ways of doing things, and are not perfectly interaccessible. Under such circumstances it could be
true that the way to get yourself to figure out a problem is to tickle your
ear with it, to get that part of your brain which is best stimulated by hearing
a question to work on the problem. Then sometimes you will find yourself with
the answer you seek on the tip of your tongue.
This
would be enough to establish the evolutionary endorsement (which might well
be only culturally transmitted) of the behavior of talking to yourself. But as many writers have observed, conscious
thinking seems--much of it--to be a variety of particularly efficient and
private talking to oneself. The evolutionary transition to thought is then
easy to conjure up. All we have to suppose is that the route, the circuit
that at first went via mouth and ear, got shorter. People
"realized" that the actual vocalization and audition was a rather
inefficient part of the loop. Besides, if there were other people around who
might overhear it, you might give away more information than you wanted. So
what developed was a habit of subvocalization, and
this in turn could be streamlined into conscious, verbal thought.
In
his posthumous book On Thinking (ed. Konstantin Kolenda,
Totowa New Jersey,
Rowman and Littlefield, 1979), Gilbert Ryle asks:
"What is Le Penseur doing?" For
behaviorists like Ryle this is a real problem. One bit of
chin-on-fist-with-knitted-brow looks pretty much like another bit, and yet
some of it seems to arrive at good answers and some of it doesn't. What can
be going on here? Ironically, Ryle, the arch-behaviorist, came up with some
very sly suggestions about what might be going on. Conscious thought, Ryle
claimed, should be understood on the model of self-teaching, or better,
perhaps: self-schooling or training. Ryle had little to say about how this
self-schooling might actually work, but we can get some initial understanding
of it on the supposition that we are not the captains of our ships;
there is no conscious self that is unproblematically
in command of the mind's resources. Rather, we are somewhat disunified. Our component modules have to act in
opportunistic but amazingly resourceful ways to produce a modicum of
behavioral unity, which is then enhanced by an illusion of greater unity.
What
Gazzaniga's research reveals, sometimes in vivid
detail, is how this must go on. Consider some of his evidence for the
extraordinary resourcefulness exhibited by (something in) the right
hemisphere when it is faced with a communication problem. In one group of
experiments, split-brain subjects must reach into a closed bag with the left
hand to feel an object, which they are then to identify verbally. The sensory
nerves in the left hand lead to the right hemisphere, whereas the control of
speech is normally in the left hemisphere, but for most of us, this poses no
problem. In a normal person, the left hand can know what the right hand is
doing thanks to the corpus collosum, which keeps both hemispheres mutually
informed. But in a split-brain subject, this unifying link has been removed;
the right hemisphere gets the information about the touched object from the
left hand, but the left, language-controlling, hemisphere must make the
identification public. So the "part which can speak" is kept in the
dark, while the "part which knows" cannot make public its
knowledge.
There
is a devious solution to this problem, however, and split-brain patients have
been observed to discover it. Whereas ordinary tactile sensations are
represented contralaterally--the signals go to the
opposite hemisphere--pain signals are also represented ipsilaterally.
That is, thanks to the way the nervous system is wired up, pain stimuli go to
both hemispheres. Suppose the object in the bag is a pencil. The right
hemisphere will sometimes hit upon a very clever tactic: hold the pencil in
your left hand so its point is pressed hard into your palm; this creates
pain, and lets the left hemisphere know there's something sharp in the bag,
which is enough of a hint so that it can begin guessing; the right hemisphere
will signal "getting warmer" and "got it" by smiling or
other controllable sings, and in a very short time "the
subject"--the apparently unified "sole inhabitant" of
the body--will be able to announce the correct answer.
Now
either the split-brain subjects have developed this extraordinarily devious
talent as a reaction to the operation that landed them with such radical
accessibility problem, or the operation reveals--but does not
create--a virtuoso talent to be found also in normal people. Surely, Gazzaniga claims, the latter hypothesis is the most
likely one to investigate. That is, it does seem that we are all virtuoso
novelists, who find ourselves engaged in all sorts of behavior, more or less
unified, but sometimes disunified, and we always
put the best "faces" on it we can. We try to make all of our
material cohere into a single good story. And that story is our
autobiography.
The
chief fictional character at the center of that autobiography is one's self.
And if you still want to know what the self really is, you're making a
category mistake. After all, when a human being's behavioral control system
becomes seriously impaired, it can turn out that the best hermeneutical story
we can tell about that individual says that there is more than one character
"inhabiting" that body. This is quite possible on the view of the
self that I have been presenting; it does not require any fancy metaphysical
miracles. One can discover multiple selves in a person just as unproblematically as one could find Early Young Rabbit
and Late Young Rabbit in the imagined Updike novels: all that has to be the
case is that the story doesn't cohere around one
self, one imaginary point, but coheres (coheres much better, in any case)
around two different imaginary points.
We
sometimes encounter psychological disorders, or surgically created
disunities, where the only way to interpret or make sense of them is to posit
in effect two centers of gravity, two selves. One isn't creating or
discovering a little bit of ghost stuff in doing that. One is simply creating
another abstraction. It is an abstraction one uses as part of a theoretical
apparatus to understand, and predict, and make sense of, the behavior of some
very complicated things. The fact that these abstract selves seem so robust
and real is not surprising. They are much more complicated theoretical
entities than a center of gravity. And remember that even a center of gravity
has a fairly robust presence, once we start playing around with it. But no
one has ever seen or ever will see a center of gravity. As David Hume noted,
no one has ever seen a self, either.
"For
my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I
always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light
or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself
at any time without a perception, and never can observe anything but the
perception.... If anyone, upon serious and unprejudiced reflection, thinks he
has a different notion of himself, I must confess I can reason no
longer with him. All I can allow him is, that he may be in the right as well
as I, and that we are essentially different in this
particular. He may, perhaps, perceive something simple and continued, which
he calls himself; though I am certain there
is no such principle in me." (Treatise on Human Nature, I, IV,
sec. 6.)
(This
article is based on my summary remarks at the 1983 Houston Symposium on the
nature of the self and consciousness. It also draws fairly heavily, and without
specific citation, on several recent papers of mine, in which the topics
discussed here are developed in more detail. References to these can be found
in my recent book The Intentional Stance, MIT Press, 1987, p.x.)
|