The
Teleological Argument
By
William Paley Excerpts
from Natural Theology (1800) Chapter
1: “State of the Argument”
In
crossing a heath, suppose I pitched my foot against a stone and were
asked how the stone came to be there, I might possibly answer that for
anything I knew to the contrary it had lain there forever; nor would it,
perhaps, be very easy to show the absurdity of this answer. But suppose I had
found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the watch
happened to be in that place, I should hardly think of the answer which I had
before given, that for anything I knew the watch might have always been
there. Yet why should not this answer serve for the watch as well as for the
stone? Why is it not as admissible in the second case as in the first? For
this reason, and for no other, namely, that when we come to inspect the
watch, we perceive -- what we could not discover in the stone -- that its
several parts are framed and put together for a purpose, e.g., that they are
so formed and adjusted as to produce motion, and that motion so regulated as
to point out the hour of the day; that if the different parts had been
differently shaped from what they are, of a different size from what they
are, or placed after any other manner or in any other order than that in
which they are placed, either no motion at all would have been carried on in
the machine, or none which would have answered the use that is now served by
it. To reckon up a few of the plainest of these parts and of their offices,
all tending to one result; we see a cylindrical box containing a coiled
elastic spring, which, by its endeavor to relax itself, turns round the box.
We next observe a flexible chain -- artificially wrought for the sake of
flexure -- communicating the action of the spring from the box to the fusee.
We then find a series of wheels, the teeth of which catch in and apply to
each other, I. Nor
would it, I apprehend, weaken the conclusion, that we had never seen a watch
made -- that we had never known an artist capable of making one -- that we
were altogether incapable of executing such a piece of workmanship ourselves,
or of understanding in what manner it was performed; all this being no more
than what is true of some exquisite remains of ancient art, of some lost
arts, and, to the generality of mankind, of the more curious productions of
modern manufacture. Does one man in a million know how oval frames are
turned? Ignorance of this kind exalts our opinion of the unseen and unknown
artist's skiff, if he be unseen and unknown, but raises no doubt in our minds
of the existence and agency of such an artist, at some former time and in
some place or other. Nor can I perceive that it varies at all the inference,
whether the question arise concerning a human agent or concerning an agent of
a different species, or an agent possessing in some respects a different
nature. II. Neither, secondly, would it invalidate our conclusion,
that the watch sometimes went wrong or that it seldom went exactly right. The
purpose of the machinery, the design, and the designer might be evident, and
in the case supposed, would be evident, in whatever way we accounted for the
irregularity of the movement, or whether we could account for it or not. It
is not necessary that a machine be perfect in order to show with what design
it was made: still less necessary, where the only question is whether it were
made with any de- sign at all. III. Nor, thirdly, would it bring any uncertainty into the
argument, if there were a few parts of the watch,, concerning which we could
not discover or had not yet discovered in what manner they conduced to the
general effect; or even some parts, concerning which we could not ascertain
whether they conduced to that effect in any manner whatever. For, as to the first
branch of the case, if by the loss, or disorder, or decay of the parts in
question, the movement of the watch were found in fact to be stopped, or
disturbed, or retarded, no doubt would remain in our minds as to the utility
or intention of these parts, although we should be unable to investigate the
manner according to which, or the connection by which, the ultimate effect
depended upon their action or assistance; and the more complex is the
machine, the more likely is this obscurity to arise. Then, as to the second
thing supposed, namely, that there were parts which might be spared without
prejudice to the movement of the watch, and that we had proved this by
experiment, these superfluous parts, even if we were completely assured that
they were such, would not vacate the reasoning which we had instituted concerning
other parts. The indication of contrivance remained, with respect to them,
nearly as it was before. IV. Nor, fourthly, would any man in his senses think the
existence of the watch with its various machinery accounted for, by being
told that it was one out of possible combinations of material forms; that
whatever he had found in the place where he found the watch, must have
contained some internal configuration or other; and that this configuration
might be the structure now exhibited, namely, of the works of a watch, as
well as a different structure. V. Nor, fifthly, would it yield his inquiry more
satisfaction, to be answered that there existed in things a principle of
order, which had disposed the parts of the watch into their present form and
situation. He never knew a watch made by the principle of order; nor can he
even form to himself an idea of what is meant by a principle of order
distinct from the intelligence of the watchmaker. VI. Sixthly, he would be surprised to hear that the mechanism
of the watch was no proof of contrivance, only a motive to induce the mind to
think so: VII. And not less surprised to be informed that the watch in
his hand was nothing more than the result of the laws of metallic
nature. It is a perversion of language to assign any law as the efficient,
operative cause of any thing. A law presupposes an agent, for it is only the
mode according to which an agent proceeds: it implies a power, for it is the
order according to which that power acts. Without this agent, without this
power, which are both distinct from itself, the law does nothing, is
nothing. The expression, "the law of metallic nature," may sound
strange and harsh to a philosophic ear; but it seems quite as justifiable as
some others which are more familiar to him, such as "the law of
vegetable nature," "the law of animal nature," or, indeed, as
"the law of nature" in general, when assigned as the cause of
phenomena, in exclusion of agency and power, or when it is substituted into
the place of these. VIII. Neither, lastly, would our observer be driven out of his
conclusion or from his confidence in its truth by being told that he knew
nothing at all about the matter. He knows enough for his argument; he knows
the utility of the end; he knows the subserviency and adaptation of the means
to the end. These points being known, his ignorance of other points, his
doubts concerning other points affect not the certainty of his reasoning. The
consciousness of knowing little need not beget a distrust of that which he
does know. Chapter
2: “State of the Argument Continued”
Suppose,
in the next place, that the person who found the watch should after some time
discover that, in addition to all the properties which he had hitherto
observed in it, it possessed the unexpected property of producing in the
course of its movement another watch like itself -- the thing is conceivable;
that it contained within it a mechanism, a system of parts -- a mold, for
instance, or a complex adjustment of lathes, baffles, and other tools --
evidently and separately calculated for this purpose; let us inquire what
effect ought such a discovery to have upon his former conclusion. I. The first effect would be to increase his admiration of
the contrivance, and his conviction of the consummate skill of the contriver.
Whether he regarded the object of the contrivance, the distinct apparatus,
the intricate, yet in many parts intelligible mechanism by which it was
carried on, he would perceive in this new observation nothing but an
additional reason for doing what he had already done -- for referring the
construction of the watch to design and to supreme art. If that construction without
this property, or, which is the same thing, before this property had been
noticed, proved intention and art to have been employed about it, still more strong
would the proof appear when he came to the knowledge of this further
property, the crown and perfection of all the rest. II. He would reflect, that though the watch before him were, in
some sense, the maker of the watch, which, was fabricated in the course
of its movements, yet it was in a very different sense from that in which a
carpenter, for instance, is the maker of a chair -- the author of its
contrivance, the cause of the relation of its parts to their use. With
respect to these, the first watch was no cause at all to the second; in no
such sense as this was it the author of the constitution and order, either of
the arts which the new watch contained, or of the parts by the aid and
instrumentality of which it was produced. We might possibly say, but with
great latitude of expression, that a stream of water ground corn; but no
latitude of expression would allow us to say, no stretch of conjecture could
lead us to think that the stream of water built the mill, though it were too
ancient for us to know who the builder was. What the stream of water does in
the affair is neither more nor less than this: by the application of an
unintelligent impulse to a mechanism previously arranged, arranged
independently of it and arranged by intelligence, an effect is produced,
namely, the corn is ground. But the effect results from the arrangement. The
force of the stream cannot be said to be the cause or author of the effect,
still less of the arrangement. Understanding and plan in the formation of the
mill were not the less necessary for any share which the water has in
grinding the corn; yet is this share the same as that which the watch would
have contributed to the production of the new watch, upon the supposition
assumed in the last section. Therefore, III. Though it be now no longer probable that the individual
watch which our observer had found was made immediately by the hand of an
artificer, yet does not this alteration in anyway affect the inference that
an artificer had been originally employed and concerned in the production.
The argument from design remains as it was. Marks of design and contrivance
are no more accounted for now than they were before. In the same thing, we
may ask for the cause of different properties. We may ask for the cause of
the color of a body, of its hardness, of its heat; and these causes may be
all different. We are now asking for the cause of that subserviency to a use,
that relation to an end, which we have remarked in the watch before us. No
answer is given to this question by telling us that a preceding watch
produced it. There cannot be design without a designer; contrivance without a
contriver; order without choice; arrangement without anything capable of
arranging; subserviency and relation to a purpose without that which could
intend a purpose; means suitable to an end, and executing their office in
accomplishing that end, without the end ever having been contemplated or the
means accommodated to it. Arrangement, disposition of parts, subserviency of
means to an end, relation of instruments to a use imply the presence of
intelligence and mind. No one, therefore, can rationally believe that the
insensible, inanimate watch, from which the watch before us issued, was the
proper cause of the mechanism we so much admire in it -- could be truly said
to have constructed the instrument, disposed its parts, assigned their
office, determined their order, action, and mutual dependency, combined their
several motions into one result, and that also a result connected with the utilities
of other beings. All these properties, therefore, are as much unaccounted for
as they were before.
The
question is not simply, How came the first watch into existence? which
question, it may be pretended, is done away by supposing the series of
watches thus produced from one another to have been infinite, and
consequently to have had no such first for which it was necessary to
provide a cause. This, perhaps, would have been nearly the state of the
question, if nothing had been before us but an unorganized, unmechanized
substance, without mark or indication of contrivance. It might be difficult
to show that such substance could not have existed from eternity, either in
succession -- if it were possible, which I think it is not, for unorganized
bodies to spring from one another -- or by individual perpetuity. But that is
not the question now. To suppose it to be so is to suppose that it made no
difference whether he had found a watch or a stone. As it is, the metaphysics
of that question have no place; for, in the watch which we are examining are
seen contrivance, design, an end, a purpose, means for the end, adaptation to
the purpose. And the question which irresistibly presses upon our thoughts
is, whence this contrivance and design? The thing required is the intending
mind, the adapting hand, the intelligence by which that hand was directed.
This question, this demand is not shaken off by increasing a number or
succession of substances destitute of these properties; nor the more, by
increasing that number to infinity. If it be said that, upon the supposition
of one watch being produced from another in the course of that other's
movements and by means of the mechanism within it, we have a cause for the
watch in my hand, namely, the watch from which it proceeded; I deny that for
the design, the contrivance, the suitableness of means to an end, the
adaptation of instruments to a use, all of which we discover in the watch, we
have any cause whatever. It is in vain, therefore, to assign a series of such
causes or to allege that a series may be carried back to infinity; for I do
not admit that we have yet any cause at all for the phenomena, still less any
series of causes either finite or infinite. Here is contrivance but no
contriver; proofs of de- sign, but no designer. The
conclusion which the first examination of the watch, of its works,
construction, and movement, suggested, was that it must have had, for cause
and author of that construction, an artificer who understood its mechanism
and designed its use. This conclusion is invincible. A second
examination presents us with a new discovery. The watch is found, in the
course of its movement, to produce another watch similar to itself; and not
only so, but we perceive in it a system of organization separately calculated
for that purpose. What effect would this discovery have or ought it to have
upon our former inference? What, as has already been said, but to increase
beyond measure our admiration of the skill which had been employed in the
formation of such a machine? Or shall it, instead of this, all at once turn
us round to an opposite conclusion, namely, that no art or skill whatever has
been concerned in the business, although all other evidences of art and skill
remain as they were, and this last and supreme piece of art be now added to
the rest? Can this be maintained without absurdity? Yet this is atheism. . .
. Chapter
5: “Application of the Argument Continued”
Every
observation which was made in our first chapter concerning the watch may be
repeated with strict propriety concerning the eye, concerning animals,
concerning plants, concerning, indeed, all the organized parts of the works
of nature. As, I. When we are inquiring simply after the existence
of an intelligent Creator, imperfection, inaccuracy, liability to disorder,
occasional irregularities may subsist in a considerable degree without
inducing any doubt into the question; just as a watch may frequently go
wrong, seldom perhaps exactly right, may be faulty in some parts, defective
in some, without the smallest ground of suspicion from thence arising that it
was not a watch, not made, or not made for the purpose ascribed to it. When
faults are pointed out, and when a question is started concerning the skill
of the artist or dexterity with which the work is executed, then, indeed, in
order to defend these qualities from accusation, we must be able either to
expose some intractableness and imperfection in the materials or point out
some invincible difficulty in the execution, into which imperfection and
difficulty the matter of complaint may be resolved; or, if we cannot do this,
we must ad- duce such specimens of consummate art and contrivance proceeding
from the same hand as may convince the inquirer of the existence, in the case
before him, of impediments like those which we have mentioned, although, what
from the nature of the case is very likely to happen, they be unknown and
unperceived by him. This we must do in order to vindicate the artist's skill,
or at least the perfection of it; as we must also judge of his intention and
of the provisions employed in fulfilling that intention, not from an instance
in which they fail but from the great plurality of instances in which they
succeed. But, after all, these are different questions from the question of
the artist's existence; or, which is the same, whether the thing before us be
a work of art or not; and the questions ought always to be kept separate in
the mind. So likewise it is in the works of nature. Irregularities and
imperfections are of little or no weight in the consideration when that
consideration relates simply to the existence of a Creator. When the argument
respects His attributes, they are of weight; but are then to be taken in
conjunction-the attention is not to rest upon them, but they are to be taken
in conjunction with the unexceptionable evidence which we possess of skill,
power, and benevolence displayed in other instances; which evidences may, in
strength, number, and variety, be such and may so overpower apparent
blemishes as to induce us, upon the most reasonable ground, to believe that
these last ought to be referred to some cause, though we be ignorant of it,
other than defect of knowledge or of benevolence in the author. . . . |