The Ethics of War
By Bertrand Russell
International
Journal of Ethics, Vol. 25
No. 2 (January, 1915). 127–142.
The
question whether war is ever justified, and if so under what circumstances,
is one which has been forcing itself upon the attention of all thoughtful
men. On this question I find myself in the somewhat painful position of
holding that no single one of the combatants is justified in the present war,
while not taking the extreme Tolstoyan view that war is under all
circumstances a crime. Opinions on such a subject as war are the outcome of
feeling rather than of thought: given a man's emotional temperament, his
convictions, both on war in general, and on any particular war which may
occur during his lifetime, can be predicted with tolerable certainty. The
arguments used will be mere reinforcements to convictions otherwise reached.
The fundamental facts in this as in all ethical questions are feelings; all
that thought can do is to clarify and systematize the expression of those
feelings, and it is such clarifying and systematizing of my own feelings that
I wish to attempt in the present article.
I.
The question of rights
and wrongs of a particular war is generally considered from a juridical or
quasi-juridical standpoint: so and so broke such and such a treaty, crossed
such and such a frontier, committed such and such technically unfriendly
acts, and therefore by the rules it is permissible to kill as many of his
nation as modern armaments render possible. There is a certain unreality, a
certain lack of imaginative grasp about this way of viewing matters. It has
the advantage, always dearly prized by lazy men, of substituting a formula,
at once ambiguous and easily applied, for the vital realization of the
consequences of acts. The juridical point of view is in fact an illegitimate
transference, to the relations of States, of principles properly applicable
to the relation of individuals within a State. Within a State, private war is
forbidden, and the disputes of private citizens are settled, not by their own
force, but by the force of the police, which, being overwhelming, very seldom
needs to be explicitly displayed. It is necessary that there should be rules
according to which the police decide who is to be considered in the right in
a private dispute. These rules constitute law. The chief gain derived from
the law and the police is the abolition of private wars, and this gain is
independent of the question whether the law as it stands is the best
possible. It is therefore in the public interest that the man who goes
against the law should be considered in the wrong, not because of the
excellence of the law, but because of the importance of avoiding the resort
to force as between individuals within the State.
In the interrelation of States
nothing of the same sort exists. There is, it is true, a body of conventions
called international law, and there are innumerable treaties between
High Contracting Powers. But the conventions and the treaties differ from
anything that could properly be called law by the absence of sanction: there
is no police force able or willing to enforce their observance. It follows
from this that every nation concludes multitudes of divergent and
incompatible treaties, and that, in spite of the high language one sometimes
hears, the main purpose of the treaties is in actual fact to afford the sort
of pretext which is considered respectable for engaging in war with another
Power. A Power is considered unscrupulous when it goes to war without
previously providing itself with such a pretext--unless indeed its opponent
is a small country, in which case it is only to be blamed if that small
country happens to be under the protection of some other Great Power. England
and Russia may partition Persia immediately after guaranteeing its integrity
and independence, because no other Great Power has a recognized interest in
Persia, and Persia is one of those small States in regard to which treaty
obligations are not considered binding. France
and Spain, under a similar
guarantee as to Morocco,
must not partition it without first compensating Germany,
because it is recognized that, until such compensation has been offered and
accepted, Germany, though
not Morocco,
has a legitimate interest in the preservation of that country. All Great
Powers having guaranteed the neutrality of Belgium, England has a recognized
right to resent its violation--a right which is exercised when it is believed
to be to England's interest, and waived when England's interest is not
thought to be involved. A treaty is therefore not to be regarded as a
contract having the same kind of binding force as belongs to private
contracts; it is to be regarded merely as a means of giving notice to rival
powers that certain acts may, if the national interest so demand, form one of
those reasons for war which are recognized as legitimate. If the faithful
observance of treaties were a frequent occurrence, like the observance of
contracts, the breach of a treaty might be a real and not merely a formal
ground for war, since it would tend to weaken the practice of deciding
disputes by agreement rather than by armed force. In the absence of such a
practice, however, appeal to treaties is only to be regarded as part of the
diplomatic machinery. A nation whose diplomacy has been skillfully conducted
will always, when it belies that its interests demand war, be able to find
some treaty or agreement bringing its intervention within the rules of the
diplomatic game. It is obvious, however, that, so long as treaties are only
observed when it is convenient to do so, the rules of the diplomatic game
have nothing to do with the question whether embarking or participating in a
war will or will not be for the good of mankind, and it is this question
which has to be decided in considering whether a war is justified or not.
II.
It is necessary, in
regard to any war, to consider, not its paper justification in past agreements,
but its real justification in the balance of good which it is to bring to
mankind. At the beginning of a war each nation, under the influence of what
is called patriotism, believes that its own victory is both certain and of
great importance to mankind. The praiseworthiness of this belief has become
an accepted maxim of common sense: even when war is actually in progress it
is held to be natural and right that a citizen of an enemy country should
regard the victory of his side as assured and highly desirable. By
concentrating attention upon the supposed advantages of the victory of our
own side, we become more or less blind to the evils inseparable from war and
equally certain whichever side may ultimately prove victorious. Yet so long
as these are not fully realized, it is impossible to judge justly whether a
war is or is not likely to be beneficial to the human race. Although the
theme is trite, it is necessary therefore briefly to remind ourselves what
the evils of war really are.
To begin with the
most obvious evil: large numbers of young men, the most courageous and the
most physically fit in their respective nations, are killed, bringing great
sorrow to their friends, loss to the community, and gain only to themselves.
Many others are maimed for life, some go mad, and others become nervous
wrecks, mere useless and helpless derelicts. Of those who survive many will
be brutalized and morally degraded by the fierce business of killing, which,
however much it may be the soldier's duty, must shock and often destroy the
more humane instincts. As every truthful record of war shows, fear and hate
let loose the wild beast in a not inconsiderable proportion of combatants,
leading to strange cruelties, which must be faced, but not dwelt upon if
sanity is to be preserved.
Of the evils of war
to the non-combatant population in the regions where fighting occurs, the
recent misfortunes of Belgium
have afforded an example upon which it is not necessary to enlarge. It is
necessary, however, to point out that the misfortunes of Belgium do not, as is commonly believed in England,
afford a reason in favor of war. Hatred, by a tragic delusion, perpetuates
the very evils from which it springs. The sufferings of Belgium are attributed to the
Germans and not to war; and thus the very horrors of war are used to
stimulate the desire to increase their area and intensity. Even assuming the
utmost humanity compatible with the conduct of military operations, it cannot
be doubted that, if the troops of the Allies penetrate into the industrial
regions of Germany, the
German population will have to suffer a great part of the misfortunes which Germany has inflicted upon Belgium. To men under the
influence of hate this thought is a cause of rejoicing, but to men in whom
humane feeling is not extinct it shows that our sympathy with Belgium should make us hate war rather than Germany.
The evils which war
produces outside the area of military operations are perhaps even more
serious, for though less intense they are far more widespread. Passing by the
anxiety and sorrow of those whose sons or husbands or brothers are at the
front, the extent and consequences of the economic injury inflicted by war
are much greater than is usually realized. It is common to speak of economic
evils as merely material, and of desire for economic progress as groveling
and uninspired. This view is perhaps natural in well-to-do people, to whom
economic progress means setting up a motor car or taking holidays in Scotland
instead of at the seaside. But with regard to the poorer classes of society,
economic progress is the first condition of many spiritual goods and even
often of life itself. An overcrowded family, living in a slum in conditions
of filth and immorality, where half the children die from ignorance of hygiene
and bad sanitation, and the remainder grow up stunted and ignorant--such a
family can hardly make progress mentally or spiritually, except through an
improvement in its economic condition. And without going to the very bottom
of the social scale, economic progress is essential to the possibility of
good education, of a tolerable existence for women, and of that breadth and
freedom of outlook upon which any solid and national advance must be based.
It is not the most oppressed or the most ill-used who make an effective plea
for social justice, for some reorganization of society which shall give less
to the idler and more to the common man. Throughout the Napoleonic wars,
while the landowners of England
continually increased their rent-rolls, the mass of the wage-earning
population sank into greater and greater destitution. It was only afterwards,
during the long peace, that a less unjust distribution began to be possible.
It cannot be doubted that the desire on the part of the rich to distract
men's minds from the claims of social justice has been more or less
unconsciously one of the motives leading to war in modern Europe.
Everywhere the well-to-do and the political parties which represent their
interests have been the chief agents in stirring up international hatred and
in persuading the working man that his real enemy is the foreigner. Thus war,
and the fear of war, has a double effect in retarding social progress: it
diminishes the resources available for improving the condition of the
wage-earning classes, and it distracts men's minds from the need and
possibility of general improvement by persuading them that the way to better
themselves is to injure their comrades in some other country. It is as a
protest against this delusion that international socialism has arisen, and
whatever may be thought of socialism as an economic doctrine, its
internationalism makes it the sanest force in modern politics, and the only
body which has preserved some degree of judgment and humanity in the present
chaos.
Of all the evils of
war the greatest, in my opinion, is the purely spiritual evil: the hatred,
the injustice, the repudiation of truth, the artificial conflict, where, if
once the blindness of atavistic instincts and the sinister influence of
anti-social interests, such as those of armaments with their subservient
press, could be overcome, it would be seen that there is a real consonance of
interest and essential identity of human nature, and every reason to replace
hatred by love. Mr. Norman Angell has well shown how unreal, as applied to
the conflicts of civilized States, is the whole vocabulary of international
conflict, how illusory are the gains supposed to be obtained by victory, and
how fallacious are the injuries to which nations, in times of peace, are
supposed to inflict upon each other in economic competition. The importance
of this thesis lies, not so much in its direct economic application, as in
the hope which it affords for the liberation of better spiritual impulses in
the relations of different communities. To love our enemies, however
desirable, is not easy; and therefore it is well to realize that the enmity
springs only from blindness, not from any inexorable physical necessity.
III.
Are there any wars
which achieve so much for the good of mankind as to outweigh all the evils we
have been considering? I think there have been such wars in the past, but
they are not wars of the sort with which our diplomatists are concerned, for
which our armies and navies have been prepared, and which are exemplified by
the present conflict. For the purposes of classification we may roughly
distinguish four kinds of wars, though of course in any given case a war is
not likely to be quite clearly of any one of the four kinds. With this
proviso we may distinguish: (1) Wars of Colonization; (2) Wars of Principle;
(3) Wars of Self-defense; (4) Wars of Prestige. Of these four kinds I should
say that the first and second are fairly often justified; the third seldom,
except against an adversary of inferior civilization, and the fourth, which
is the sort to which the present war belongs, never. Let us consider these
four kinds of war in succession.
By
a war of colonization I mean a war whose purpose is to drive out the
whole population of some territory and replace it by an invading population
of a different race. Ancient wars were very largely of this kind, of which we
have a good example in the Book of Joshua. In modern times the conflicts of
Europeans with American-Indians, Maoris, and other aborigines in temperate
regions, have been of this kind. Such wars are totally devoid of technical
justification, and are apt to be more ruthless than any other war.
Nevertheless, if we are to judge by results, we cannot regret that such wars
have taken place. They have the merit, often quite fallaciously claimed for
all wars, of leading in the main to the survival of the fittest, and it is
chiefly through such wars that the civilized portion of the world has been
extended from the neighborhood of the Mediterranean to the greater part of the
earth's surface. The eighteenth century, which liked to praise the virtues of
the savage and contrast them with the gilded corruption of courts,
nevertheless had no scruple in thrusting the noble savage out from his North
American hunting grounds. And we cannot at this date bring ourselves to
condemn the process by which the American continent has been acquired for
European civilization. In order that such wars may be justified, it is
necessary that there should be a very great and undeniable difference between
the civilization of the colonizers and that of the dispossessed natives. It
is necessary also that the climate should be one in which the invading race
can flourish. When these conditions are satisfied the conquest becomes
justified, though the actual fighting against the dispossessed inhabitants
ought, of course, to be avoided as far as is compatible with colonizing. Many
humane people will object in theory to the justification of this form of
robbery, but I do not think that any practical or effective objection is
likely to be made.
Such wars, however,
belong now to the past. The regions where the white men can live are all
allotted, either to white races or to yellow races to whom the white man is
not clearly superior, and whom, in any case, he is not strong enough to
expel. Apart from small punitive expeditions, wars of colonization, in the
true sense, are no longer possible. What are nowadays called colonial wars do
not aim at the complete occupation of a country by a conquering race; they
aim only at securing certain governmental and trading advantages. They
belong, in fact, rather with what I call wars of prestige, than with wars of
colonization in the old sense. There are, it is true, a few rare exceptions.
The Greeks in the second Balkan war conducted a war of colonization against
the Bulgarians; throughout a certain territory which they intended to occupy,
they killed all the men, and carried off all the women. But in such cases,
the only possible justification fails, since there is no evidence of superior
civilization on the side of the conquerors.
In spite, however,
of the fact that wars of colonization belong to the past, men's feelings and
beliefs about war are still those appropriate to the extinct conditions which
rendered such wars possible. When the present war began, many people in England imagined that if the Allies were
victorious Germany would
cease to exist; Germany
was to be destroyed or smashed, and since these phrases sounded
vigorous and cheering, people failed to see that they were totally devoid of
meaning. There are some seventy million Germans; with great good fortune, we
might, in a successful war, succeed in killing two millions of them. There
would then still be sixty-eight million Germans, and in a few years the loss
of population due to the war would be made good. Germany is not merely a State,
but a nation, bound together by a common language, common traditions, and
common ideals. Whatever the outcome of the war, this nation will still exist
at the end of it, and its strength cannot be permanently impaired. But the
imagination in what pertains to war is still dominated by Homer and the Old
Testament; men who cannot see that circumstances have changed since those
works were composed are called practical men and are said to be free
from illusions. Those, on the other hand, who have some understanding of the
modern world, and some capacity for freeing their minds from the influence of
phrases, are called dreamy idealists, Utopians, traitors, and friends of
every country but their own. If the facts were understood, wars amongst
civilized nations would case, owing to their inherent absurdity. Men's
passions always lag behind their political organizations, and facts which
leave no outlet for passions are not readily admitted. In order that hatred,
pride, and violence may find an outlet, men unconsciously blind themselves to
the plainest facts of politics and economics, and modern war continues to be
waged with the phrases and theories invented by simpler men in a simpler age.
IV.
The second type of
war which may sometimes be justified is what may be called the war of
principle. To this kind belong the wars of Protestant and Catholic, and
the English and American civil wars. In such cases, each side, or at least
one side, is honestly convinced that the progress of mankind depends upon the
adoption of certain beliefs--beliefs which, through blindness or natural
depravity, mankind will not regard as reasonable, except when presented at
the point of the bayonet. Such wars may be justified: for example, a nation
practicing religious toleration may be justified in resisting a persecuting
nation holding a different creed. On this ground we might justify the
resistance of the Dutch to the England and French combined in
the time of Charles II. But wars of principle are much less often justified
than is believed by those in whose age they occur. It is very rarely that a
principle of genuine value to mankind can only be propagated by military
force: as a rule, it is the bad part of men's principles, not the good part,
which makes it necessary to fight for their defense. And for this reason the
bad part rather than the good rises to prominence during the progress of a
war of principle. A nation undertaking a war in defense of religious toleration
would be almost certain to persecute those of its citizens who did not
believe in religious toleration. A war on behalf of democracy, if it is long
and fierce, is sure to end in the exclusion from all share of power of those
who do not support the war. Mr. George Trevelyan in an eloquent passage
describes the defeat which, as the ultimate outcome of our civil war,
overtook alike the ideals of the Roundheads and the ideals of the Cavaliers. And this was the curse of the
victors, not to die, but to live, and almost to lose their awful faith in
God, when they saw the Restoration, not of the old gaiety that was too gay
for them and the old loyalty that was too loyal for them, but of corruption
and selfishness that had neither country nor king. The sound of the Roundhead
cannon has long ago died away, but still the silence of the garden is heavy
with unalterable fate, brooding over besiegers and besieged, in such haste to
destroy each other and permit only the vile to survive. This
common doom of opposite ideals is the usual, though not the invariable,
penalty of supporting ideals by force. While it may therefore be conceded that
such wars are not invariably to be condemned, we must nevertheless scrutinize
very skeptically the claim of any particular war to be justified on the
ground of the victory which it brings to some important principle.
There are some who
maintain that the present war is a war in defense of democracy. I do not know
whether this view is adopted by the Tsar, and for the sake of the stability
of the Alliance
I sincerely hope that it is not. I do not, however, desire to dispute the
proposition that democracy in the western nations would suffer from the
victory of Germany.
What I do wish to dispute is the belief not infrequently entertained in England that if the Allies are victorious
democracy can be forced upon a reluctant Germany as part of the conditions
of peace. Men who think thus have lost sight of the spirit of democracy in
worship of the letter. The Germans have the form of government which they
desire, and therefore any other form, imposed by alien victors, would be less
in harmony with the spirit of democracy, however much it might conform to the
letter. Men do right to desire strongly the victory of ideals which they
believe to be important, but it is almost always a sign of yielding to undue
impatience when men believe that what is valuable in their ideals can be
furthered by the substitution of force for peaceful persuasion. To advocate
democracy by war is only to repeat, on a vaster scale and with far more
tragic results, the error of those who have sought it hitherto by the
assassin's knife and the bomb of the anarchist.
Russell, n.
1. George M. Trevelyan, Clio, A Muse, and other Essays
literary and pedestrian, London,
1913, pp. 26–27. ↩
V.
The
next kind of war to be considered is the war of self-defense. This kind of
war is almost universally admitted to be justifiable, and is condemned only
by Christ and Tolstoy. The justification of wars of self-defense is very
convenient, since so far as I know there has never yet been a war which was
not one of self-defense. Every strategist assures us that the true defense is
offence; every great nation believes that its own overwhelming strength is
the only possible guarantee of the world's peace and can only be secured by
the defeat of other nations. In the present war, Serbia is defending itself
against the brutal aggression of Austria-Hungary; Austria-Hungary is
defending itself against the disruptive revolutionary agitation which Serbia
is believed to have fomented; Russia is defending Slavdom against the menace
of Teutonic aggression; Germany is defending Teutonic civilization against
the encroachments of the Slav; France is defending itself against a
repetition of 1870; and England, which sought only the preservation of the status quo, is defending itself against a prospective
menace to its maritime supremacy. The claim of each side to be fighting in self-defense
appears to the other side mere wanton hypocrisy, because in each case the
other side believes that self-defense is only to be achieved by conquest. So
long as the principle of self-defense is recognized as affording always a
sufficient justification for war, this tragic conflict of irresistible claims
remains unavoidable. In certain cases, where there is a clash of differing
civilizations, a war of self-defense may be justified on the same grounds as
a war of principle. I think, however, that, even as a matter of practical
politics, the principle of non-resistance contains an immense measure of
wisdom if only men would have the courage to carry it out. The evils suffered
during a hostile invasion are suffered because resistance is offered: the Duchy
of Luxemburg, which was not in a position to offer resistance, has escaped
the fate of the other regions occupied by hostile troops. What one civilized
nation can achieve against another by means of conquest is very much less
than is commonly supposed. It is said, both here and in Germany, that each
side is fighting for its existence; but when this phrase is scrutinized, it
is found to cover a great deal of confusion of thought induced by unreasoning
panic. We cannot destroy Germany
even by a complete military victory, nor conversely, could Germany destroy England
even if our Navy were sunk and London
occupied by the Prussians. English civilization, the English language,
English manufactures would still exist, and as a matter of practical politics
it would be totally impossible for Germany to establish a tyranny in
this country. If the Germans, instead of being resisted by force of arms, had
been passively permitted to establish themselves wherever they pleased, the
halo of glory and courage surrounding the brutality of military success would
have been absent, and public opinion in Germany itself would have
rendered any oppression impossible. The history of our own dealings with our
colonies affords abundant examples to show that under such circumstances the
refusal of self-government is not possible. In a word, it is the means of
repelling hostile aggression which make hostile aggression disastrous and
which generate the fear by which hostile nations come to think aggression
justified. As between civilized nations, therefore, non-resistance would seem
not only a distant religious ideal, but the course of practical wisdom. Only
pride and fear stand in the way of its adoption. But the pride of military
glory might be overcome by a nobler pride, and the fear might be overcome by
a clearer realization of the solidity and indestructibility of a modern
civilized nation.
VI.
The last kind of
war we have to consider is what I have called the war of prestige.
Prestige is seldom more than one element in the causes of a war, but it is
often a very important element. In the present war, until the war had
actually broken out, it was almost the only thing involved, although as soon
as the war began other and much more important matters came to be at stake.
The initial question between Austria
and Russia
was almost wholly one of prestige. The lives of Balkan peasants could not
have been much affected for good or evil by the participation or
non-participation of Austrian officials in the trial of supposed Serbian
accomplices in the Sarajevo
murders. This important question, which is the one on which the war is being
fought, concerns what is called the hegemony of the Balkans, and this is
entirely a question of prestige. Men desire the sense of triumph, and fear
the sense of humiliation which they would have in yielding to the demands of
another nation. Rather than forego the triumph, rather than endure the
humiliation, they are willing to inflict upon the world all those disasters
which it is now suffering and all that exhaustion and impoverishment which it
must long continue to suffer. The willingness to inflict and endure such
evils is almost universally praised; it is called high-spirited, worthy of a
great nation, showing fidelity to ancestral traditions. The slightest sign of
reasonableness is attributed to fear, and received with shame on the one side
and with derision on the other. In private life exactly the same state of
opinion existed so long as dueling was practiced, and exists still in those
countries in which this custom still survives. It is now recognized, at any
rate in the Anglo-Saxon world, that the so called honor which made
dueling appear inevitable was a folly and a delusion. It is perhaps not too
much to hope that the day may come when the honor of nations, like that of
individuals, will be longer measured by their willingness to inflict
slaughter. It can hardly be hoped, however, that such a change will be
brought about while the affairs of nations are left in the keeping of
diplomatists whose status is bound up with the diplomatic or military triumph
of the countries from which they come, and whose manner of life renders them
unusually ignorant of all the political and economic facts of real importance
and of all the changes of opinions and organization which make the present
world different from that of the eighteenth century. If any real progress is
to be made in introducing sanity into international relations, it is vital
that these relations should be in the hands of men less aloof and less
aristocratic, more in touch with common life, and more emancipated from the
prejudices of a bygone age. It is necessary also that popular education,
instead of inflaming the hatred of foreigners and representing even the
tiniest triumph as worthy of even the greatest sacrifices, should aim rather
at producing some sense of the solidarity of mankind and of the paltriness of
those objects to which diplomatists, often secretly, think fit to pledge the
manhood and heroism of nations.
The objects for
which men have fought in the past, whether just or unjust, are no longer to
be achieved by wars amongst civilized nations. A great weight of tradition,
of financial interests, of political insincerity, is bound up with the
anachronism of international hostility. It is, however, perhaps not
chimerical to hope that the present war, which has shocked the conscience of
mankind more than any war in previous history, may produce a revulsion
against antiquated methods, and may lead the exhausted nations to insist upon
the brotherhood and co-operation which their rulers have hitherto denied
them. There is no reason whatever against the settlement of all disputes by a
Council of Powers deliberating in public. Nothing stands in its way except
the pride of rulers who wish to remain uncontrolled by anything higher than
their own will. When this great tragedy has worked itself out to its
disastrous conclusion, when the passions of hate and self-assertion have
given place to compassion with the universal misery, the nations will perhaps
realize that they have fought in blindness and delusion, and that the way of
mercy is the way of happiness for all.

|